August 15, 2000
No Experience Necessary:
Empiricism, Non-inferential Knowledge, and Secondary Qualities
Empiricism can be a view in epistemology: without
perceptual experience, we can have no knowledge of contingent matters of
fact. Empiricism can be a view in
semantics: propositional or more generally conceptual content is unintelligible
apart from its relation to perceptual experience. Empiricism can be a view in the philosophy of mind:
"experience must constitute a tribunal, mediating the way our thinking is
answerable to how things are, as it must be if we are to make sense of it as
thinking at all."[1] The most important development in empiricism
in recent decades[2] is
McDowell's Mind and World. The view he puts forward there is empiricist
in all these senses. In this essay I
want to highlight certain features of his concept of experience, first by
showing how he avoids some pitfalls that notoriously ensnare traditional
attempts to work out empiricist intuitions, and second by comparing and contrasting
it with two other ways of construing perceptual experience—one less committive
than McDowell's and the other more so—that also avoid the classical
difficulties. The stripped-down view is
the one I endorse. It is epitomized by
my title: No Experience Necessary.
Indeed, though the word "experience" is mentioned in the 750
pages of Making It Explicit, it is
never used. I want to say, with Laplace
[check this!], "Je n'ai pas besoin de cette hypothèse la." The explanatory work done by what Sellars has
taught us is the theoretical concept experience
can be done without postulating a layer of potentially evidentially significant
(hence conceptually articulated) states in between purely causally occasioned
and physiologically specifiable responses to environing stimuli and full-blown
perceptual judgments. Even were he to
grant this claim, the realist McDowell would, I think, insist that
nevertheless, perceptual experiences that are not yet judgments are there, and therefore deserve theoretical recognition. I think that such realism about perceptual
experiences commits its adherents to there being answers to the sorts of
questions I will raise under the heading of the more committive views, which
McDowell also resists.
I
McDowell's empiricism is distinguishable from
classical versions in at least two fundamental ways. First, with Kant and Sellars, McDowell understands experience as
a thoroughly conceptual
achievement. Thus he insists that
anything that does not have concepts does not have perceptual experience
either. Because he does, McDowell
counts also as endorsing the fundamental rationalist
insight: that to be aware of something in the sense in which such awareness can
serve as evidence for beliefs amounting to knowledge is to bring it under a concept. This principle dictates that one must
already have concepts in order to have experience in the sense he is
addressing—a sense that in view of its fealty to the rationalist principle
deserves to be seen as a successor of Leibniz’ notion of apperception.
McDowell also insists that anything that does not
have perceptual experience does not have concepts either. That is, he endorses the view I called
semantic empiricism above. Concept use
and perceptual experience are two aspects of one achievement. This view
was emphatically not a feature of traditional rationalism. In his synthesis of these themes of
classical rationalism and classical empiricism, as in so many other respects,
McDowell is a kantian.
Second, for McDowell perceptual experience is
generally (though not in every case) immediately and essentially revelatory of
empirical facts. That is, it is
essential to McDowell's concept of perceptual experience that the fact that
things are thus and so can be the
content of a perceptual experience.
When things go well, the fact itself is visible to us. It is
the content we experience. The
perceiving mind includes what it perceives.
Because he understands perceptual experience as
requiring the grasp of concepts, McDowell avoids the Myth of the Given, which
afflicts all classical versions of epistemological empiricism. The Myth of the Given is the claim that
there is some kind of experience the having of which does not presuppose grasp
of concepts, such that merely having
the experience counts as knowing
something, or can serve as evidence
for beliefs, judgments, claims, and so on, that such a nonconceptual experience
can rationally ground, and not just
causally occasion, belief. In
"Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind"[3],
Sellars shows to McDowell's satisfaction (and to mine) that the project of
making intelligible a concept of experience that is in this way amphibious
between the nonconceptual world and our conceptually structured thought is a
hopeless one. By contrast, McDowell is
clear in taking perceptual experiences to have the same sort of content that
perceptual judgments have—and hence
to be conceptually structured.
Since McDowell also takes concept use to be a linguistic achievement (in line with
Sellars' doctrine that to grasp a concept is to master the use of a word), he
takes it that we learn to have perceptual experiences only when we come to have
a language. Thus perceptual experience
is not something we share with
nonlinguistic animals such as cats and chimpanzees. No doubt there is some sort of broadly perceptual attunement to
things that we do share with our
primate and mammalian cousins. We might
call it ‘sentience’. But it will not
qualify as experience, according to
McDowell's rationalist usage. We might
call the capacity for experience in this sense ‘sapience’. As a consequence, McDowell insists that we
cannot understand what we have, perceptual experiences, by construing it as the
result of starting with what we share with our sentient but not sapient animal
relatives, and then adding something
(say, the ability to use concepts). For
what we would need to 'add' is not itself intelligible apart from the notion of
perceptual experience.[4]
Other thinkers who are careful to avoid the Myth of
the Given do so by placing the interface between nonconceptual causal stimuli
and conceptual response at the point where environing stimuli cause perceptual judgments. That is, they avoid the Myth by seeing nothing nonjudgmental that
could serve to justify perceptual
judgments, rather than just to cause
them. Davidson notoriously takes this
line, endorsing the slogan that nothing but a belief can justify another
belief. I would argue that Sellars
himself has a view of this shape.[5] And it is the line I take in my book.[6] McDowell, however, construes perceptual
experiences as not involving the sort of endorsement
characteristic of judging or believing: perceptual experiences have judgeable,
believable contents, but they are not judgments or beliefs. When a perceiver does advance from perceptual experience to judgment or belief,
however, the experience can serve to justify the resulting commitment.
I said above that the second feature that
distinguishes McDowell's view of perceptual experience from those appealed to
by empiricists of a more traditional stripe is his view that in favored cases,
when perception is veridical, the content of perceptual experience just is the fact perceived. McDowell endorses the Fregean approach,
which construes facts as true thoughts—'thoughts' not in the
psychological sense of thinkings, but in the semantic sense of the contents that are thought, or better,
thinkable. The obvious pitfall in the
vicinity of such a view is the need to deal with the fact that we make
perceptual mistakes. That is, we sometimes cannot tell the
difference between the case in which we are having a perceptual experience
whose content is a fact and cases where there is no such fact to be
perceived. Traditionally, the
explanatory strategy for addressing such phenomena had the shape of a two factor theory: one starts with a
notion of perceptual experience as what is common
to the veridical and the nonveridical cases, and then distinguishes them by adding something external to the
experience: the truth of the claim, that is, the actual existence of the fact
in question. Epistemologically, this
strategy sets the theorist up for the Argument from Illusion, and hence for a
skeptical conclusion. McDowell's
objection to the two factor strategy is not epistemological, however, but
semantic. It is not that it makes the
notion of perceptual knowledge
unintelligible (though it does that, too).
It is that it makes unintelligible the notion of objective purport—our experiences (and therefore, our thoughts) so
much as seeming to be about the
perceptible world. He thinks that
constraint can only be met by an account that is entitled to endorse what is
perhaps his favorite quote from Wittgenstein:
“When we say, and mean that
such-and-such is the case, we—and our meaning—do not stop anywhere short of the
fact; but we mean: this-is-so.”[7] McDowell's perceptual realism is his way of
explaining how this can be so.
Extending the doctrine of semantic empiricism, he thinks that if we
can't make this feature of our thought and talk intelligible for perceptual
experience, then we can't make it intelligible for any claims or beliefs.
On his view, the only
thing a veridical perceptual experience and a corresponding hallucination have
in common is that their subject can't tell them apart. There is no experience in common. We
just are not infallible about the contents of our experiences, and can confuse
being in the state of having one for being in the state of having another—for
instance by responding to each by endorsing the same perceptual judgment. Once again, he insists, we cannot understand
veridical experience by construing it as the result of starting with a notion
of what is common to the state that prompts a veridical perceptual judgment and
the state that prompts a corresponding mistaken perceptual judgment, and then adding something (say, the truth of the
claim in question).[8]
The various features of McDowell's view that I have
focused on are related. The revelation
of perceptible fact in perceptual experience is 'immediate' in the sense that
the conceptual abilities required (by the first condition above) are exercised passively in perception. They are the very same conceptual abilities
exercised actively in, say, making a judgment as the result of an inference,
but differ in that the application of concepts in perceptual experience is
wrung from us involuntarily by the perceptible fact. The way in which concepts are brought passively into play falls
short of judgment or belief, however.
The content is presented to the potential knower as a candidate for endorsement. But an act of judgment is required to
endorse it. So what is wrung from us by
the facts is not judgments, but only petitions for judgments.
McDowell thinks it is important to maintain this
distinction in order to make intelligible the sense in which we are rationally responsible for our perceptual
judgments. I agree that it is essential
to make sense of that responsibility.
But I do not see that doing that requires postulating in the standard
case an advance from merely entertained judgeable-but-not-yet-endorsed content
to endorsement or judgment. The fact
that the passively arrived at judgments, once they are on board, are open to
criticism in the light of collateral commitments—which is what being "on
board" in the relevant sense means—seems to me entirely sufficient as an
account of what our rational responsibility consists in. Indeed, liability to this sort of criticism
is the primary sense McDowell himself associates with the kantian concept of spontaneity
in Mind and World. I worry that in this regard he has fallen in
unnecessarily and incorrectly with the pre-Kantian tradition that saw a prior,
independently intelligible act of will as required prior to assessments of
responsibility—a picture of a cloud of merely entertained judgeable contents
awaiting the exercise of an act of will by which we plump for some of them.[9]
II
I want to situate McDowell's notion of perceptual
experience by placing it with respect to two other notions, one broader than
his and one narrower. The broader
notion is non-inferential knowledge
acquired in response to environing stimuli. The narrower notion is that of immediate awareness of secondary qualities.
I said above that thinkers such as Davidson, who
reject the Myth of the Given, have typically rejected also the idea of any
conceptually structured intermediary between causal stimuli and full-blown
observational judgments. McDowell
thinks that we need to postulate perceptual experiences, which are such
intermediaries—though we must be clear that they are intermediaries only in the
straightforward causal sense of being brought about by environing stimuli and
bringing about observational judgments, not in the sense of the sort of
epistemological intermediaries that give rise to the picture of a “veil of
ideas”. His view is clearly coherent,
and is not subject to the objections Davidson forwards against epistemological
intermediaries as classically conceived.
But we might still ask what explanatory ground is gained by countenancing
perceptual experiences, since we can avoid the Myth of the Given without
them. One part of McDowell’s answer is
that his notion of experience lets us distinguish cases of genuine perception
from other cases of responsively acquired noninferential knowledge. I want to sketch an account of this broader
class, and then say why McDowell thinks we must also distinguish a privileged
species within this genus.
Quine suggests[10]
that what distinguishes specifically observational
knowledge is that observation reports are reliably keyed to environing stimuli
in a way that is widely shared within some community—so that members of that
community almost always agree about what to say when concurrently stimulated in
the same way. This suggests that we
think of there being two elements one needs to master in order to be able to
make a certain kind of observation report, two distinguishable sorts of
practical know-how involved. First, one
must have a acquired a reliable
differential responsive disposition: a disposition reliably to respond
differentially to some kind of stimulus.
Which stimuli we can come differentially to respond to depends on how we
are wired up and trained. Humans lack
the appropriate physiology to respond differentially to different radio
frequencies, for instance, without technological aids. Blind mammals cannot respond differentially
to colors. These capacities are
something we can share with nonconceptual creatures such as pigeons—or as far
as that goes, with photocells and thermostats.
Second, one must have the capacity to produce conceptually articulated responses: to respond to red things not
just by pecking at one button or closing one circuit rather than another, but
by claiming that there is something
red present. I think we should
understand this latter capacity as the ability to take up a certain kind of
stance in the space of reasons: to make a move in what Sellars calls “the game
of giving and asking for reasons” of a sort that can both serve as and stand in
need of reasons. A parrot could be
taught to respond to red things by uttering the noise “That’s red,” but it would not be saying or claiming that
anything was red. I think we can
understand what it is lacking as the ability to tell what it would be
committing itself to by such a claim, and what would entitle it to that
commitment—that is, what follows from the claim that something is red (for
instance, that it is colored and spatially extended) and what would be evidence
for it (for instance that it is scarlet) or against it (for instance, that it
is green). But nothing in what follows
depends on this particular way of understanding the dimension of endorsement
that distinguishes observational reports from mere differential responses.
If it turns out that I can reliably differentially
respond to a certain sort of state of affairs by noninferentially reporting the
presence of a state of affairs of that sort, and if I know that I am reliable
in this way, then I think that true reports of this kind deserve to be called observationally
acquired knowledge. This is in some ways a fairly radical
view—though, I think, a defensible one.
For one consequence of thinking of observation this way is that there is
no particular line to be drawn between what is in principle observable and what
is not. The only constraints are what a
reporter can be trained under some circumstances reliably to differentiate, and
what concepts she can then key the application of to those responsive
dispositions. Thus a properly trained
physicist, who can respond systematically differently to differently shaped
tracks in a cloud chamber will, if she responds by noninferentially reporting
the presence of mu mesons, count as genuinely observing those subatomic particles. She may start out by reporting the presence of hooked vapor
trails and inferring the presence of
mu mesons, but if she then learns to eliminate the intermediate response and
respond directly to the trails by reporting mesons, she will be observing
them. “Standard conditions” for observing
mu mesons will include the presence of the cloud chamber, just as standard
conditions for observing the colors of things includes the presence of adequate
light of the right kind. And the
community for whom ‘mu meson’ is an observation predicate will be much smaller
and more highly specialized than the community for whom ‘red’ is one. But these are differences of degree, rather
than kind.
Again, it may be that if challenged about a
noninferential report of a mu meson, our physicist would retreat to an inferential justification, invoking the shape of the
vapor trail that prompted her report.
But we need not understand that retreat as signifying that the original
report was, after all, the product of an inference. Rather, the claim of the presence of a mu
meson, which was noninferentially elicited as a direct response to a causal
chain that included (in the favored cases) both mu mesons and vapor trails (but
which was a report of mu mesons and not vapor trails—or retinal
irradiations—because of the inferential role of the concept that was applied in it) can be justified inferentially
after the fact by appealing to a safer
noninferential report, regarding the shape of the visible vapor trail. This report is safer in the dual sense that
first, the physicist is more reliable reporting the shapes of vapor trails than
she is the presence of mu mesons (since the latter are more distal in the
causal chain of reliably covarying events that culminate in the report, so
there is more room for things to go wrong) and second, the capacity reliably to
report the presence of vapor trails of various shapes is much more widely
shared among various reporters than is the capacity reliably to report the
presence of mu mesons (even in the presence of a cloud chamber). The practice of justifying a challenged
report by retreating to a safer one, from which the original claim can then be
derived inferentially, should not (certainly need not) be taken to indicate that the original report was itself
covertly the product of a process of inference.
As I would use the terms, following out the
rationalist principle that I take McDowell also to endorse, to be aware of
something (in the sense relevant to assessments of sapience) is just to apply a
concept to it—that is, to make a judgment or undertake a doxastic commitment
regarding it. Awareness deserves to be
called ‘immediate’ just in case it is not the product of a process of
inference. Thus, beliefs acquired
noninferentially, by the exercise of reliable dispositions to respond differentially
to stimuli of a certain sort by making corresponding reports (‘corresponding’
in the sense that what is reported is some element of the causal chain of
reliably covarying events that culminates in the report in question) embody immediate awareness of the items
reported. The first contrasting view
(null hypothesis) with respect to which I want to place McDowell’s view is then
that this is the only sense of
‘immediate awareness’ we need in order to understand our perceptual knowledge
of the world around us.
If we press this picture of observation as
consisting just in the exercise of reliable differential responsive
dispositions to apply concepts[11],
even more outré examples present themselves.
Suppose that at least some people can be conditioned to discriminate
male from female newly hatched chicks, just by being corrected until they
become reliable. They have no idea what
features of the chicks they are presented with they are responding
differentially to, but they not only become reliable, they also come to know that they are reliable. When one of them noninferentially responds
to a chick by classifying it as male, if he is correct, I think he has
observational knowledge of that fact.
(And I think McDowell is prepared to agree.) This can be so even if it is later discovered (I’m told that this
is true) that the chicken sexers are wrong in thinking that they are
discriminating the chicks visually—that
in fact, although they are not aware of it, the discrimination is being done on
an olfactory basis. According to this way of thinking about
observation, what sense is in play can only
be discriminated by discovering what sorts of alterations of conditions degrade
or improve the performance of the reliable reporters. If altering light levels does not change their reliability, but
blocking their noses does, then they are working on the basis of scent, not of
sight.[12]
McDowell thinks that although there can be cases of
what is in a broad sense observational
knowledge like this [if even that seems too generous, mark this very special
sense by calling it "Bobservation"], they must be sharply
distinguished from cases of genuine perceptual
knowledge, for instance being able to see shapes or colors. That is, he rejects the suggestion that the
latter be assimilated to the former.
When we see colors and shapes, we have perceptual experiences corresponding to the judgments we go on to make or the
beliefs we go on to form. The chicken
sexers in my example do not have perceptual experiences of chicks as male or
female. They just respond blindly, though they have learned to
trust those blind responses. There is
for them no appearance of the chicks as male or female.
Put another way, McDowell is committed to there
being two kinds of beliefs acquired
noninferentially by the exercise of reliable dispositions to respond
differentially to stimuli by reporting elements of the causal chain that
culminates in the report. In genuine
perception, the belief is the result of endorsing
the content of a perceptual experience. In the other sort (what might be called
‘mere observation’) the belief is acquired blindly, that is in the absence of a
perceptual experience with the same content.
Under the right circumstances, one just finds oneself with the belief in
question. But this sort of belief
formation is not a case of facts becoming visible (or more generally,
perceptible) to us. Although these
beliefs are noninferentially elicited from the believer by environmental
stimuli, the warrant for those beliefs is in an important sense
inferential. The believer’s
justification for beliefs of this sort depends on drawing conclusions from an
antecedent claim of reliability. In
this respect, the believer herself is in no different position than a
third-person observer would be.
There is certainly an intuitive appeal to this
distinction. But I worry whether its
appeal is merely intuitive, or
whether there is important explanatory work for the distinction to do. After all, we have lots of residually
cartesian intuitions. This worry is a
pragmatic one, in the spirit of Quine’s query in “Two Dogmas of Empiricism”
concerning what features of our linguistic practice—the way we actually use
language—reflect or are explained by the distinction of claims into analytic
and synthetic. Intuitions that are
quite possibly (I’m inclined to say necessarily)
infected by prior theoretical commitments are not to the point here. Once properly trained, we just find
ourselves responding to visible red things by calling them red. And in this usage, ‘visible’ need mean no
more than ‘in standard conditions for visual observation’, that is, in good
light, on an unoccluded sight line to the observer, and so on.
Once we have relinquished the Myth of the Given, we
must be careful not to assimilate the making of such noninferential judgments
to the identification of something by criteria. I may apply the concept ‘white oak’ to a tree because I have
noticed the characteristic bilaterally symmetrically roundly-lobed leaves. It makes sense to ask how I knew that it was
a white oak, and an answer can be given.
But in the case of red things, there is no set of features I am
noticing, from which I conclude that they are red. I can just tell red things by looking at them. If there weren’t some features like this,
there couldn’t be any empirical knowledge of the sort exemplified by my white
oak judgment either. I can say that the
patch looks red, in a sense of ‘looks’ that is no more committive than that
involved in saying I can tell red things by looking at them. That is the only sense in which the world
need appear to me as anything.
In “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind”, Sellars
offers a recipe for introducing ‘looks’ or ‘appears’ talk, wherever there is a
noninferential reporting practice. Whenever a reporter suspects her own reliability under certain
conditions of observation, she can express
her usually reliable disposition to report something as being f, but withhold
her endorsement of that claim, by
saying only that it looks (or appears) f. The chicken sexers are certainly able to introduce ‘looks’ and
‘appears’ talk in this way. But
McDowell’s claim is then that there is an important difference between such uses
of these locutions and their use to report perceptual experiences. He thinks that the capacity to have
perceptual experiences is different from, and more fundamental than, the
capacity to make noninferential observations of mu mesons in cloud chambers and
of the sexes of chickens. Unless we
could have perceptual experiences, we could not make any observations at
all—even though not all observations of a state of affairs involve perceptual
experiences of those states of affairs.
That is, the capacity to become noninferentially informed about the
world by learning blindly to respond
differentially to it depends upon a more basic capacity for states of affairs
to become immediately apparent in perception.
Thus it is important to McDowell to distinguish a notion of conceptually
structured perception that is narrower
than the merely responsive notion of conceptually structured observation I have
sketched.
I asked above, in a pragmatic spirit, about what
explanatory work such a distinction does for us. McDowell has a response, of course. It is that without the notion of conceptually articulated
perceptual experience that distinguishes genuine perception from merely
responsively acquired noninferential belief, we cannot understand the empirical
content of any of our claims. For without that notion, we are doomed to
embrace one horn of the dilemma from which Mind
and World sets out to free us. In
McDowell’s view, the picture of observation I have been suggesting may be all
we need substitutes mere causal
constraint by the world for the genuinely rational
constraint that is required for us to make intelligible to ourselves the idea
of our beliefs as about the world
without us. For that notion of
aboutness requires that our beliefs answer rationally
for their correctness to the facts they purport to present, not merely that
they are causally occasioned by them.
This way of working out semantic empiricism presents deep and important
issues, which I cannot pursue here. (I
have addressed some of them in a preliminary fashion elsewhere.[13])
Rather than press that set of global philosophical
issues, I focus here on the distinction McDowell is obliged to draw between
genuine perception and what I have been calling ‘mere observation’
["Bobservation"] to raise a much more local and limited issue. What sort of a fact is it that in some cases
where we noninferentially acquire a true belief by exercising a reliable
disposition noninferentially to respond to the fact in question by acquiring
the belief there is a perceptual experience present, while in others there is
not? How would we go about settling the
question of whether the physicist has genuine perceptual experiences of mu
mesons? Is there any way in principle
to tell other than asking her? And if
we do ask her, is there any chance that she is wrong, because she has been
taught a bad theory? Could I think I
was having perceptual experiences of mu mesons or the maleness of chickens when
I was not, or vice versa? Do we know
just by having a perceptual experience what sensory modality it corresponds to
(so that the—supposed—fact that the chicken sexers get this wrong is decisive
evidence that they do not have genuine perceptual experiences)? The answers to questions such as these
determine just how classically cartesian McDowell’s notion of perceptual
experience is—and so, from my point of view, just how suspicious we should be
of it. I do not assert that his answers
to these questions will be Cartesian ones.
I don’t know how to answer them, and do not find much help in Mind and World.
III
Putting
things in terms of how the world appears to us raises a danger of getting
McDowell wrong in the other direction, however. For a natural response to the sort of distinction of cases on
which I am claiming McDowell insists—at least for philosophers familiar with
the empiricist tradition McDowell is extending—is to think that what sets off
mere observation of the sort epitomized by the mu meson and chicken sexing
cases from genuine perception is that the physicist and the chicken sexer are
not reporting their awareness of any secondary
qualities. Being a mu meson or a
male chick are primary qualities, and so not directly or immediately
experienceable in the sense in which secondary qualities such as red are. For traditional empiricism took it that our awareness of the
perceptible world is, as it were, painted
in secondary qualities: qualities that nothing outside the mind can literally
have, purely experiential properties more or less reliably induced in minds as
the effects of external bodies.[14] These secondary qualities correlate with,
and so represent features of
perceptible objects. But since they are
merely the effects those features have on suitably prepared and situated minds,
they do not present properties
literally exhibited by the objects themselves.
Phenomena of this sort, the secondary qualities of things, are all that is directly or immediately
perceivable. Coming to know about
anything else is the result of making inferences
from the occurrence of the experiences of secondary qualities they occasion in
us.
Following Gareth Evans, McDowell has endorsed a
pragmatic account of the distinction between secondary and primary
qualities. (By calling it ‘pragmatic’ I
mean to indicate that it defines the distinction in terms of differences in the
use of expressions for—predicates used
to attribute the occurrence of—secondary and primary qualities.) According to this way of understanding
things, to take f to express a secondary
quality concept is to take it that one cannot count as having mastered the use
of ‘f’ talk[15]
unless one has also mastered the use of ‘looks-f’ talk. This criterion distinguishes predicates such
as ‘red’, which express secondary qualities, from those such as ‘square’, which
express primary qualities. For one does
not count as fully understanding the concept red unless one knows what
it is for things to look red. While a blind geometer can count as fully understanding the concept square even if
she cannot discriminate one by looking at it.
According to the minimally committive account of observation sketched above,
one can learn ‘looks-f’ talk just in case one has
mastered the noninferential
circumstances of appropriate application of the concept f—that
is, just in case one has both mastered the inferential role of the
concept, and has been trained into the reliable differential responsive
dispositions that key its noninferential application to the apparent presence
of the reported state of affairs.[16]
Since McDowell’s ‘minimal empiricism’[17]
seeks to rehabilitate what was right in the appeals to experience that
motivated classical empiricism, it is tempting to understand his distinction
between genuine perceptual experience and mere noninferential observation of
environing circumstances in terms of the role of secondary qualities in the
former. Perceptual experience, the
thought would run, is always experience immediately of secondary qualities.
That is what is missing in the mu meson and chicken sexing case. (Not that there are not secondary qualities
involved in those cases, but rather that what is reported in those cases is not
the occurrence of secondary qualities.)
But this would be to misunderstand McDowell’s position. For he thinks we can have perceptual experience of some primary qualities, not just secondary
ones. Thus shapes, for instance, can be
visible and tangible—genuinely the subjects of perceptual experience. Where there are perceptual experiences,
there are appearances, which can be reported by the use of ‘looks’ talk. And since McDowell admits that a certain attenuated form of
‘looks’ talk applies even to mere
observation, without corresponding perceptual experiences, it should be marked
that in these cases it will be ‘looks’ talk in the stronger sense. But the existence of perceptual experiences
that are being reported by such ‘looks’ talk does not require that the mastery
of such talk is an essential feature of mastery of the concepts being
applied. Talk of perceptual experiences
is not a way of talking about secondary qualities. All immediate awareness of secondary qualities involves
perceptual experiences, but not necessarily vice
versa.
Here it is important to keep in mind a distinction
between two different ways in which one might understand the Evans-McDowell
characterization of secondary qualities in terms of ‘looks’-talk. I claimed above that Sellars gives us a
recipe for introducing a use of ‘looks-j’ (or, more generally,
‘appears-j’) corresponding to any
predicate j that has a noninferential
reporting use. According to this
understanding, there is no problem with the physicist talking about things
looking like mu mesons, or the chicken sexer talking about things looking like
(or appearing to be) male chicks. If
the Evans-McDowell criterion for being a secondary quality concept is combined
with this understanding of the use of ‘looks’ (or ‘appears’), then what results
is the notion of concepts that are essentially
observable—in the sense that in order fully to master the concept, one must
have mastered its noninferential
circumstances of application. Red is pretty clearly like this, and mu meson is pretty clearly not like
this. But just as we can introduce a
use for ‘looks to be a mu meson’, we could also introduce another concept,
which is just like mu meson except
that mastery of the noninferential use of the expression, and of the
corresponding ‘looks’ locution, is
required for certification as having mastered that concept. And similarly for any merely observational
property. This fact may suggest that
the notion of essentially observable
[Bobservable] concept should not be
identified with the classical notion of secondary
quality concept.
In fact, this is McDowell’s view. For this reason, he does not understand the
appeal to ‘looks’ in the definition of secondary qualities in the minimal
Sellarsian sense identified above. For
in this sense, there could be experience of secondary qualities where there are
no corresponding perceptual experiences in his sense. And he is committed to perceptual experiences being necessary, though not sufficient, for
awareness of secondary qualities.
McDowell understands the responsive use of ‘looks-j’ locutions as genuine reports—not, as on the minimal Sellarsian line rehearsed above,
merely expressions of dispositions to make endorsements one is not in fact
making. What ‘looks’ claims report (at
least in the central cases) is just perceptual experiences.
I have situated McDowell’s notion of perceptual
experience between a broader notion and a narrower one—between the concept of
knowledge noninferentially acquired by applying concepts as the result of
reliable differential responsive dispositions, and the concept of immediate
awareness of secondary qualities. As I
pointed out above, McDowell denies that the broader concept of merely
noninferential knowledge is independent of that of perceptual experience: if we
could not have perceptual experiences, then we could not know things
noninferentially at all. (Indeed, he
thinks we could not know anything at
all.) I would like to end this
discussion with a question, his answer to which I have not been able to
determine from McDowell’s writings:
Could there be perceptual experience, for McDowell, if there were no
secondary qualities? That is, could
anyone have perceptual experiences of primary qualities if she could not also
have perceptual experiences of secondary qualities? If not, why not? If so,
what would it be like? And once again,
what sort of questions are these? How
ought one to go about addressing them?
Is it a matter for introspection, or for empirical investigation? If purely philosophical argumentation is
needed, what are the criteria of adequacy according to which we should assess
the answers?
IV
In closing, I would like to add a further
query. If we look at the end of Mind and World, we see that we can have
non-inferential knowledge of normative
facts: of meanings, for instance, and of how it is appropriate to act. Coming to be able to make such
non-inferential judgments is part of being brought up properly, part of
acquiring our second nature. Along
something like the same lines, in his earlier writings, McDowell has urged (in
opposition to Davidson’s interpretational view) that fully competent speakers
of a language do not infer the
meanings of others’ utterances from the noises they make, rather they directly
or immediately hear those
meanings. Coming to speak the language
is coming to be able to perceive the
meanings of the remarks of other speakers of it. The connection I have in mind between these claims is that claims
about what someone means are normative claims.
They have consequences concerning what she has committed herself to, what she is responsible for, what it would take for her claim to be correct, and so on. So McDowell’s view is that normative facts are noninferentially
knowable.
It has always seemed to me to be one of the great
advantages of the account of observational knowledge in terms of reliable
differential responsive dispositions to apply concepts noninferentially that it
makes perfect sense of these claims. If
I have mastered the use of some normative vocabulary (whether pertaining to
meanings, or to how it is proper to behave nonlinguistically), and if I can be
trained reliably to apply it noninferentially, as a differential response to
the occurrence of normatively specified states of affairs, then I can have
observational knowledge of those normative states of affairs: I can see (or at least perceive[18]) what
it is appropriate to do or say.
Normative concepts are no worse off than concepts like mu meson
in terms of their capacity to acquire observational uses. So here is my final question for
McDowell: is this mere non-inferential knowledge?
Or are the normative statuses also perceptually experienceable, for
McDowell? I don't think he commits
himself on this, any more than he does on the question of whether secondary
qualities are necessary for experience.
Indeed, one could ask further:
are there (can there be) secondary qualities corresponding to essentially
normative states of affairs that are noninferentially knowable?
I think that these are important questions in their
own right. It seems to me a virtue of
McDowell’s writings about sense experience that it brings such questions into
view. I am also inclined to think that
I do not fully understand McDowell’s concept of perceptual experience until I
know how it bears on this sort of question.
McDowell does not address himself to these questions, and I do not know
what he would say about them if he did.
I do suspect[19]
that his response will be in the form of deflection: Interesting questions though these might be, the project of Mind and World does not require that
they be addressed. For the project of
that work is heavily diagnostic and lightly therapeutic, but not at all
theoretical. Its task is not, as its author understands it, to
present a theory of content, or of
perceptual experience. It is rather to
make evident to its readers the common presuppositions powering an oscillation
between two equally unsatisfactory ways of talking about the role of experience
in empirical thought. It aims further
at giving us some instruction in how we might talk once we have freed ourselves
from attachment to those fatal philosophical assumptions that structure so much
of the tradition by which we have been shaped.
Doing that does not, the claim would be, require taking a stand on every
potentially controversial issue that could arise in the vicinity once we have
thrown off the fetters in which commitment to defective (though after Mind and World intelligibly and
forgiveably tempting) ways of thinking about nature and the relation between
causal and rational constraint have bound us.
The response I am putting in McDowell’s mouth has
considerable force. But in the end, I
do not find it satisfactory. It seems
to me that the therapeutic dimension of the enterprise of Mind and World involves a commitment to there being at least some satisfactory way of extending the
things he has said about observation, perception, and sensory experience so as
to answer the sort of questions our following out of his remarks has
raised. For instance, he is committed
to there being a distinction between two sorts of noninferentially acquired
knowledge of states of affairs: in one kind there is an experience of that state of affairs, and in the other not. But, we should ask, does this distinction
manifest itself in any way or explain anything outside the confines of the
theory? (Compare Quine’s corresponding
question about the analytic/synthetic distinction.) Or is it real only in the way the question of whether socinianism
is a heresy once had to be taken seriously, because until it was settled we
wouldn’t know who the true Pope is? I
think the issue of whether the ways McDowell has recommended we talk about
perceptual experience can be extended so as to afford sensible answers to the
sorts of questions I have argued his discussion implicitly raises delineates a
fair dimension along which the adequacy of his story should be appraised.
McDowell’s bold and ingenious rehabilitation of the
empiricists’ concept of experience requires us to make conceptual distinctions
far subtler than any the tradition worried about. He also gives us the conceptual raw materials to make those
distinctions clear. This is all pure
advance. I have sought here to rehearse
some of these distinctions, and to use them to invite McDowell to commit
himself in the terms he has provided on issues that he has not yet formally
addressed.
Bob Brandom
University of Pittsburgh
[1] Mind and World [Harvard University Press, 1994] p. xii (from the Introduction, added in the paperback edition of 1996].
[2] I would say, at least since van Fraassen's sophisticated version.
[3] Originally published in 1956, this classic essay has recently been reprinted, with an Introduction by Richard Rorty and a section by section Study Guide by Robert Brandom [Harvard University Press, 1997].
[4] In this respect he parts company with the picture I present in Making It Explicit [Harvard University Press, 1994], as he makes clear in his comments on the book in “Brandom on Inference and Representation,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LVII, No.1, March 1997, pp. 157ff.
[5] What he calls 'sense impressions' are causal antecedents of perceptual judgments, but do not serve to justify them.
[6] Making It Explicit. See especially the first half of Chapter Four.
[7] Philosophical Investigations §95.
[8] On this point, see his “Knowledge and the Internal”, and my companion piece “Knowledge and the Social Articulation of the Space of Reasons,” both in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (4), December ’95.
[9] Of course, as pointed out at the outset, McDowell breaks with this picture in rejecting the idea that we could learn merely to entertain conceptual contents first, without at the same time having endorsed many of them. But as I see it, this avoids only one of the objectionable features of this cartesian picture.
[10] In “Epistemology Naturalized”, in Ontological relativity, and other essays, [New York: Columbia University Press, 1969]
[11] I develop and defend such an account in Chapter Four of Making It Explicit.
[12] I owe this way of thinking about the difference between sensory modalities in terms of conditions of reliability to Lionel Shapiro.
[13] “Perception and Rational Constraint” in Philosophical Issues 7 1996: Perception (Sociedad Filosofica Ibero Americana—edited by Enrique Villaneuva) pp. 241-260. Abbreviated version published in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LVIII No. 2 (June 1998), pp. 369-374.
[14] Berkeley is the paradigmatic defender of such a view, but as an implicit theme, this way of thinking about secondary qualities was pervasive in pre-Kantian empiricism.
[15] Sellars glosses grasping a concept as mastering the use of a word.
[16] McDowell will insist that a richer notion of mastering ‘looks’ (or, more generally, ‘appears’) talk—one that involves the reporting of perceptual experiences, not just the conceptually structured exercise of reliable differential responsive dispositions—should be brought to bear in defining secondary qualities. But this qualification does not make a difference for the use I am making here of the Evans-McDowell characterization of secondary qualities.
[17] His characterization, in the new Introduction to the paperback edition of Mind and World.
[18] Perhaps not ‘see’ or ‘hear’, since these terms are committive as regards sense modality—commitments to be cashed out, as I indicated above, in terms of the nature of the conditions that degrade or improve reliability. Notice that in this sense it is appropriate to talk about hearing the meaning of someone’s oral utterance, and seeing the meaning of her written remark.
[19] Based on our conversations on the matter in connection with our joint seminar on Perception (University of Pittsburgh, Spring 1998).