Overcoming a Dualism of Concepts and Causes:
A Unifying Thread in "Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind”
Some of the most interesting and important metaphysics of the last 400 years addresses the nature of intentionality: our capacity to direct our activity by our beliefs about the things around us. Intentionality—the aboutness or representational character of thought—is the most fundamental feature of our mindedness. The metaphysics of intentionality during the Early Modern period has been structured by an overarching distinction that shows up in many more specific forms: body vs. mind, order of things vs. order of ideas, representings and representeds, causal vs. conceptual. A distinction qualifies as a dualism when it is drawn in a way that makes unintelligible the relations between what is distinguished, and this fundamental distinction in the metaphysics of intentionality has often threatened to become a dualism.[1] The Cartesian variety had special features that seemed to be important for the difficulties faced by the whole picture. It understood the subjective in terms of the theoretical transparency, incorrigibility, or certainty of the mental, and its practical indefeasibility, dominion, or local omnipotence. (Descartes was impressed by the fact that one can be wrong about how things are, but not about how they seem, and that while it may not be in one’s power to do something, it is always in one’s power to try to do something.) This understanding of the subjective is one of the reasons that without what can seem as a metaphysical detour through God, Descartes cannot explain how the physical world can affect our thought through perception, or how thought can affect the physical world through action. Important as his more particular ideas about subjectivity were, rejecting these features of Descartes’ view turned out to be far from sufficient to avoid the danger of commitment to various other forms of what is broadly the same sort of dualism, however. Even philosophical approaches that have rejected much of the specifically Cartesian metaphysics of the subject can have trouble with their accounts of the interactions between the causal order and the conceptual order. And this ought not to surprise us. After all, it didn’t turn out to help very much with this problem to give up the specifically Cartesian metaphysics of the physical in terms of pure extension.
The rise of modern philosophy is coeval with the rise of modern science. Descartes, of course, was a major player in both fields. He crystallized the problem that was to engage philosophers down to our own day: how to understand the place of minds in the physical world revealed to us by the new science. That was a causal world: a world, in the familiar slogan, of atoms in the void. A new kind of mathematized theoretical understanding was revealing that world to us as never before. But it was by no means clear that there was room in that emerging picture for the theorists themselves. How could understanding or thinking something be understood to fit into this picture? The activity of classifying something under the concepts of physics—as extended, with a certain size, shape, position, and motion—did not itself seem obviously to be itself intelligible in terms of the sorts of physical properties science was discovering. Intentionality is our capacity to represent things, to understand them, to think about them (including the ability to think about things that are distant in space or time, or even nonexistent). The best Descartes himself could do was to postulate the existence of a special kind of stuff, mindstuff, which was understood as essentially representative in nature—by contrast to physical stuff, which by nature could only be represented. But he was wholly unable to say how the two sorts of stuff interacted, and so unable to say anything helpful about what it is for a thought or concept to be about something in the causal order, where laws of nature hold sway. This response has been almost universally found to be unsatisfactory.
One of the most distinctive attempts to offer a new diagnosis of and therapy for the ills of broadly cartesian dualisms of the causal and the conceptual is to be found in the work of one of the great systematic metaphysicians of the mid-twentieth century: Wilfrid Sellars. Like Descartes (and Plato), his metaphysics grows out of his epistemology. The connection between the two subjects is different for him, because he does not (as Descartes does) subscribe to the platonic principle that fundamental differences in kinds of being can be read off of structural differences in the ways we know them. (For instance, for reasons discussed below, Sellars opposes the instrumentalist thought that purely theoretical objects, which are known only inferentially, are ontologically—rather than methodologically—of a different kind from observable objects, which are known perceptually.) The epistemological diagnosis that funds Sellars’ metphysical reconciliation of the causal and the conceptual is set out in his master-work: “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind” [Sellars 1956].
That essay is one of the great works of twentieth century philosophy. It is rich, deep, and revolutionary in its consequences. It cannot, however, be ranked among the most perspicuous of philosophical writings. Although it is fairly easy to discern its general tenor and tendency, the convoluted and digressive order of exposition pursued in the essay has obscured for many readers the exact outlines of such a fundamental concept as givenness—with the result that few could at the end of their reading accurately trace its boundaries and say what all its species have in common, being obliged instead to content themselves with being able to recognize some of its exemplary instances. Again, I think that partly for this reason, readers of EPM seldom realize just how radical is its critique of empiricism—just how much of traditional empiricist ways of thinking must be rejected if Sellars’ arguments are accepted. And if the full extent of the work’s conclusions is hard to appreciate, all the more difficult is it to follow its argumentative path through all its turnings. In what follows my aim is to lay out one basic idea of Sellars’, which I see as underlying three of the most important arguments he deploys along the way to his conclusions. My concern here will not be in how those arguments contribute to his overall enterprise, but rather in how they are rooted in a common thought. Sellars does not make this basic idea as explicit as one would like, and does not stop along the way to observe how each of the three individual arguments depends on it. But if I am right, we will understand the essay better by being able to identify and individuate this thread in the tapestry.
The master idea I want to start with is Sellars’ understanding of observational capacities: the ability to make noninferential reports of, or to form perceptual judgments concerning, perceptible facts. My claim is that he treats them as the product of two distinguishable sorts of abilities: the capacity reliably to discriminate behaviorally between different sorts of stimuli, and the capacity to take up a position in the game of giving and asking for reasons. The three central strategic moves in the essay I will seek to understand in terms of that two factor approach to observation are: first, the way he dissolves a particular cartesian temptation by offering a novel account of the expressive function of ‘looks’ talk; second, his rationalist account of the acquisition of empirical concepts; and third, his account of how theoretical concepts can come to have observational uses.
I. Sellars’ Two-Ply Account
of Observation
If we strip empiricism down to its core, we might identify it with the insight that knowledge of the empirical world depends essentially on the capacity of knowing organisms to respond differentially to distinct environing stimuli. I’ll call this claim ‘basic’, or ‘stripped down’ empiricism; it could equally well be called the trivial thesis of empiricism.[2] Surely no rationalist or idealist has ever denied this claim. While differential responsiveness is obviously a necessary condition for empirical knowledge, it is clearly nothing like a sufficient condition. A chunk of iron responds differentially to stimuli, for instance by rusting in some environments, and not in others. To that extent, it can be construed as classifying its environments, taking or treating them as being of one of two kinds. In the same way, as Hegel says, an animal takes something as food by “falling to without further ado and eating it up.”[3] But this sort of classificatory taking something as something should not yet be classed as a cognitive matter, on pain of losing sight of the fundamental ways in which genuine observationally acquired knowledge differs from what is exhibited by merely irritable devices such as thermostats and land mines.
A parrot could be trained to respond to the visible presence of red things by uttering the noise “That’s red.” We might suppose that it is disposed to produce this performance under just the same circumstances in which a genuine observer and reporter of red things is disposed to produce a physically similar performance. There is an important respect in which the parrot and the observer are alike. We could call what they share a reliable differential responsive disposition (which I’ll sometimes shorten to ‘RDRD’). RDRDs are the first element in Sellars’ two-ply account of observational knowledge. At least in the basic case, they are characterizable in a naturalistic, physicalistic vocabulary.[4] The concept of an RDRD is meant to capture the capacity we genuine knowers share with artifacts and merely sentient creatures such as parrots that the basic thesis of empiricism insists is a necessary condition of empirical knowledge.
The second element of Sellars’ two-ply account of observational knowledge is meant to distinguish possessors of genuine observational belief and knowledge from merely reliable differential responders. What is the crucial difference between the red-discriminating parrot and the genuine observer of red things? It is the difference between sentience and sapience. For Sellars’ purposes in EPM, the difference between merely differentially responding artifacts and genuinely sentient organisms does not make an essential cognitive or epistemological difference. All we need pay attention to in them is their exercising of reliable differential responsive dispositions. But he is very concerned with what distinguishes both of these sorts of things from genuine observers. His thought is that the difference that makes a difference is that candidates for observational knowledge don’t just have reliable dispositions to respond differentially to stimuli by making noises, but have reliable dispositions to respond differentially to those stimuli by applying concepts. The genuine observer responds to visible red things by coming to believe, claiming, or reporting that there is something red. Sapient awareness differs from awareness in the sense of mere differential responsiveness (the sort exhibited by any organism or device that can for instance be said in the full sense to be capable of avoiding obstacles) in that the sapient being responsively classifies the stimuli as falling under concepts, as being of some conceptually articulated kind.
It is obvious that everything turns on how one goes on to understand concept application or the conceptual articulation of responses. For Sellars, it is a linguistic affair: grasping a concept is mastering the use of a word. Then we must ask what makes something a use of a word, in the sense relevant to the application of concepts. Sellars’ answer is that for the response reliably differentially elicited by the visible presence of a perceptible state of affairs to count as the application of a concept, for it to be properly characterized as a reporting or coming to believe that such-and-such is the case, is for it to be the making of a certain kind of move or the taking up of a certain kind of position in a game of giving and asking for reasons. It must be committing oneself to a content that can both serve as and stand in need of reasons, that is, that can play the role both of premise and of conclusion in inferences. The observer’s response is conceptually contentful just insofar as it occupies a node in a web of inferential relations.
What the parrot lacks is a conceptual understanding of its response. That is why it is just making noise. Its response means nothing to the parrot—though it may means something to us, who can make inferences from it, in the way we do from changes in the states of measuring instruments. The parrot does not treat red as entailing colored, as entailed by scarlet, as incompatible with green, and so on. And because it does not, uttering the noise ‘red’ is not, for the parrot, the adopting of a stance that can serve as a reason committing or entitling it to adopt other stances, and potentially in need of reasons that might be supplied by still further such stances. By contrast, the observer’s utterance of ‘That’s red,’ is making a move, adopting a position, in a game of giving and asking for reasons. And the observer’s grasp of the conceptual content expressed by her utterance consists in her practical mastery of its significance in that game: her knowing (in the sense of being able practically to discriminate, a kind of knowing how) what follows from her claim and what it follows from, what would be evidence for it and what is incompatible with it.
Although Sellars does not carefully distinguish them, two different strands can be discerned within this second element of his account. First is the idea that for performances (whether noninferentially elicited responses or not) to count as claims, and so as expressions of beliefs or judgments, as candidates for knowledge, they must be in what he calls “the dimension of endorsement.”[5] This is to say that they must have a certain sort of pragmatic significance or force: they must express the endorsement of some content by the candidate knower. They must be the adoption of a certain kind of normative stance: the undertaking of a commitment. Second, that the commitment is a cognitive commitment, the endorsement of a conceptual content, is to be understood in terms of its inferential articulation, its place in the “space of reasons,” its being a move in the “game of giving and asking for reasons.”[6] This is to say at least that in making a claim one commits oneself to its suitability as a premise from which conclusions can be drawn, a commitment whose entitlement is always at least potentially liable to demands for vindication by the exhibition of other claims that can serve as reasons for it.
This two factor account of perceptual judgments (claims to observational knowledge) is a version of a broadly kantian strategy: insisting on the collaboration of capacities characterizable in terms of receptivity and spontaneity. It is a pragmatic version, since it is couched in terms of know how: practical abilities to respond differentially to nonlinguistic stimuli, and to distinguish in practice what inferentially follows from or serves as a reason for what. The residual empiricism of the approach consists in its insistence on the need for the exercise of some of our conceptual capacities to be the exercise of RDRDs. Its residual rationalism consists in its insistence that the responses in question have cognitive significance, count as applications of concepts, only in virtue of their role in reasoning. What otherwise would appear as language-entry moves, without language-language moves, are blind. What otherwise would appear as language-language moves without language-entry moves, are empty. (I say “what otherwise would appear” as moves because such blind or empty moves do not for Sellars qualify as moves in a language game at all.)[7]
It follows from this two-pronged approach that we must be careful in characterizing perceptual judgments or reports of observations as ‘noninferential’. They are noninferential in the sense that the particular acts or tokenings are noninferentially elicited. They are not the products of a process of inference, arising rather by the exercise of reliable capacities to noninferentially respond differentially to various sorts of perceptible states of affairs by applying concepts. But no beliefs, judgments, reports, or claims—in general, no applications of concepts—are noninferential in the sense that their content can be understood apart from their role in reasoning as potential premises and conclusions of inferences. Any response that does not at least potentially have an inferential significance—which cannot, for instance serve as a premise in reasoning to further conclusions—is cognitively idle: a wheel on which nothing else turns.
This rationalist claim has radical consequences. It means that there can be no language consisting only of noninferential reports, no system of concepts whose only use is in making perceptual judgments. Noninferential reports do not form an autonomous stratum of language: a game one could play though one played no other. For that they are reports or claims, expressions of beliefs or judgments, that they are applications of concepts at all, consists in their availability to serve as premises and conclusions of inferences. And this is so no matter what the subject matter of the reports might be—even if what is reported, that of which one is noninferentially aware, is one’s own current mental states. Awareness that reaches beyond mere differential responsiveness—that is, awareness in the sense that bears on cognition—is an essentially inferentially articulated affair.
So observational concepts, ones that have (at least some) noninferential circumstances of appropriate application, can be thought of as inference laden. It does not follow, by the way, that they are for Sellars for that reason also theory laden. For, as will appear below, Sellars understands theoretical concepts as those that have only inferential circumstances of appropriate application—so that noncompound claims in which they occur essentially are ones that one can only become entitled to as the result of an inference. His rationalist rendering of the notion of conceptual contentfulness in terms of role in reasoning only commits Sellars to the claim that for any concept to have noninferential uses, it must have inferential ones as well. He is prepared to countenance the possibility of an autonomous language game in which every concept has noninferential, as well as inferential uses. Such a language game would be devoid of theoretical terms.
II. ‘Looks’ Talk and Sellars’ Diagnosis of the Cartesian Hypostatization of Appearances
One
of the central arguments of EPM applies this two-legged understanding of the
use of observational concepts to the traditional understanding of claims about
how things look as reports of appearances. The question he addresses can be variously put. In one form it is the question of whether looks-red
come before is-red conceptually (and so in the order of explanation)? Put in a form more congenial and
comprehensible to a pragmatist—that is, in a form that concerns our abilities
to do something—this becomes the
question of whether the latter can be defined in terms of the former in such a
way that one could learn how to use the defining concept (looking-j) first, and only afterwards, by means of the
definition, learn how to use the defined concept (is-j)? Since
Sellars understands grasp of a concept in terms of mastery of the use of a
word, this then becomes a question about the relation between practices of
using “looks-j” talk and the practices of using “is-j” talk. This
is a relatively clear way of asking about an issue that goes to the heart of
the cartesian project of defining the ontological realm of the mental in terms
of the epistemic privileged accesss in the sense of incorrigibility of mental
occurrences.
Descartes was struck by the fact that the
appearance/reality distinction seems not to apply to appearances. While I may be mistaken about whether
something is red (or whether the
tower, in the distance, is square), I
cannot in the same way be mistaken about whether it looks red to me now.[8] While I may legitimately be challenged by a
doubter: “Perhaps the item is not really red; perhaps it only seems red,” there is no room for the further doubt, “Perhaps the item does
not even seem red; perhaps it only seems to seem red.” If it seems to seem red, then it really does
seem red. The looks, seems, or appears operators collapse if we try to
iterate them. A contrast between
appearance and reality is marked by the distinction between looks-j and j for ordinary
(reality-indicating) predicates ‘j’. But no corresponding contrast is marked by
the distinction between looks-to-look-j and looks-j. Appearances
are reified by Descartes as things that really are just however they
appear. He inferred that we do not know
them mediately, by means of representings that introduce the possibility of mis-representing (a distinction between
how they really are and how they merely appear, i.e. are represented as
being). Rather, we know them immediately—simply by having them. Thus appearings—thought of as a realm of
entities reported on by
noninferentially elicited claims about how things look (for the visual case), or more generally seem, or appear—show up
as having the ideal qualifications for epistemologically secure foundations of
knowledge: we cannot make mistakes
about them. Just having an appearance (“being appeared-to j-ly”, in one of the variations Sellars discusses) counts
as knowing something: not that something is j, to be sure, but at least that something looks-, seems-, or appears-j. The
possibility accordingly arises of reconstructing our knowledge by starting out
only with knowledge of this sort—knowledge of how things look, seem, or
appear—and building up in some way to our knowledge (if any) of how things
really are (outside the realm of appearance).
This
project requires that concepts of the form looks-j be intelligible in principle in advance of grasping
the corresponding concepts j (or is-j). Sellars argues that Descartes got things backwards. ‘Looks’ talk does not form an autonomous
stratum of the language—it is not a language-game one could play though one
played no other. One must already be
able to use ‘is-j’ talk in order to master ‘looks-j’ talk, which turns out to be parasitic on it. In this precise practical sense, is-j is conceptually
(Sellars often says ‘logically’) prior
to looks-j.
His
argument takes the form of an account of how ‘looks’ talk can arise
piggy-backed on ‘is’ talk. In EPM Sellars does not try to support the
strong modal claim that the various practices must be related in this way.
He thinks that his alternative account of the relation between these
idioms is so persuasive that we will no longer be tempted by the cartesian
picture. It is an interesting question,
which I will not pursue here, whether his story can be turned into an more
compelling argument for the stronger claim he wants to make. What he offers us is the parable of John in
the tie shop.
At
the first stage, John has mastered the noninferential use of terms such as
‘green’ and ‘blue’. So he can,
typically, reliably respond to green things by applying the concept green,
to blue things by applying the concept blue, and so on. To say that his responsive dispositions are
reliable is to say that he usually turns out to be right—so the inference from
his being disposed to call something ‘green’ or ‘blue’ to its being green or blue
is a generally good (though not infallible) one.
At
the next stage, electric lights are installed in the shop, and John discovers
that they make him prey to certain sorts of systematic errors. Often, when under the electric lights inside
his shop he observes something to be green, it turns out in fact—when he and
others examine it outside in daylight—to be blue. Here it is obviously important that John have access to some ways
of entitling himself to the claim that something is blue, besides the term he
is initially disposed to apply to it.
This can include his dispositions to respond to it outside the shop,
together with his beliefs about the circumstances in which ties do and do not
change color, the assessments of others, and the fact that the proper use of
color terms was originally keyed to daylight assessments. At this point, John becomes cautious. When viewing under the nonstandard
conditions of electric lighting, he does not indulge his otherwise reliable
disposition to respond to some visible ties by calling them green. Instead he says something like: “I’m
disposed to call this green, and if I didn’t know that under these
circumstances I’m not a reliable discriminator of green things, I would give in
to that temptation and call it green.”
At
the final stage, John learns under these circumstance to substitute the
expression “It looks green,” for this
long expression of temptation withstood.
Using the expression “looks-j” is doing two
things: first, it is evincing the same
usually reliable differential responsive disposition that in other
circumstances results in the claim that something is (. But second, it is withholding the endorsement of the claim
that something is green. In other
words, it is doing something that agrees with an ordinary non-inferential
report of green things on the first component of Sellars’ two-ply account of
observation reports—sharing an RDRD—but disagrees with it on the second
component, withholding endorsement instead of undertaking the commitment.
The
idea is that where collateral beliefs indicate that systematic error is likely,
the subject learns not to make the report 'x
is j', to which his previously inculcated responsive
dispositions incline him, but to make a new kind of claim: 'x looks
(or seems) j'. The
cartesian temptation is to take this as a new kind of report. This report then is naturally thought of as
reporting a minimal, noninferentially ascertainable, foundationally basic item,
an appearing, about which each subject is incorrigible. Sellars’ claim is that
it is a mistake to treat these as reports at all—since they evince a disposition to call something j, but do not do so.
They do not even report the
presence of the disposition—that is, they are not ways of saying that one has that disposition.
This
analysis of what one is doing in using ‘looks’ explains the incorrigibility of
‘looks’ talk. One can be wrong about
whether something is green because
the claim one endorses, the commitment one undertakes, may turn out to be
incorrect. For instance, its
inferential consequences may be incompatible with other facts one is or comes
to be in a position to know independently.
But in saying that something looks
green, one is not endorsing a claim, but withholding
endorsement from one. Such a reporter
is merely evincing a disposition to do something that for other reasons (e.g.
suspicion that the circumstances of observation lead to systematic error) he is
unwilling to do—namely, endorse a claim.
Such a reporter cannot be wrong, because he has held back from making a
commitment. This is why the looks, seems, and appears operators do not iterate. Their function is to express the withholding
of endorsement from the sentence that appears within the scope of the
operator. There is no sensible contrast
between ‘looks-to-look j’ and ‘looks-j’, of the sort there is
between ‘looks-j’ and ‘(is-j (’ because the first
‘looks’ has already withheld endorsement from the only content in the vicinity
to which one might be committed (to something’s being j). There is
no further withholding work for the second ‘looks’ to do. There is nothing left to take back. Since asserting ‘X looks j’ is not undertaking a propositionally contentful
commitment—but only expressing an overrideable disposition to do so—there is no
issue as to whether or not that commitment (which one?) is correct.
Sellars accordingly explains the
incorrigibility of appearance-claims, which had so impressed Descartes. He does so in terms of the practices of
using words, which are what grasp of the relevant appearance concepts must amount
to, according to his methodological linguistic pragmatism. But once we have seen the source and nature
of this incorrigibility—in down-to-earth, practical, resolutely nonmetaphysical
terms—we see also why it is precisely unsuited to use as an epistemological
foundation for the rest of our (risky, corrigible) empirical knowledge. For, first, the incorrigibility of claims
about how things merely look simply
reflects their emptiness: the fact that
they are not really claims at all. And
second, the same story shows us that ‘looks’ talk is not an autonomous language
game—one that could be played though one played no other. It is entirely parasitic on the practice of
making risky empirical reports of how things actually are. Thus Descartes seized on a genuine
phenomenon—the incorrigibility of claims about appearances, reflecting the
non-iterability of operators like looks,
seems, and appears—but
misunderstood its nature, and so mistakenly thought it available to play an
epistemologically foundational role for which it is in no way suited.
III. Two Confirmations of the Analysis of ‘Looks’ Talk in Terms of the Two-Ply Account of Observation
Sellars
finds that the analysis of ‘looks’ talk in terms of the two pronged account of
perceptual judgments is confirmed by its capacity to explain features of
appearance-talk that are mysterious on the contrasting cartesian approach.
i)
The apple over there is red.
ii)
The apple over there looks red.
iii) It looks as though there were a red apple over there.
Utterances
of these sentences can express the same responsive disposition to report the
presence of a red apple, but they endorse (take responsibility for the
inferential consequences of) different parts of that claim. (i) endorses both the existence of the
apple, and its quality of redness. (ii)
endorses only the existence of the apple.
The 'looks' locution explicitly cancels the qualitative commitment or
endorsement. (iii) explicitly cancels
both the existential and the qualitative endorsements. Thus, if someone claims that there is in
fact no apple over there, he is asserting something incompatible with (i) and
(ii), but not with (iii). If he denies
that there is anything red over there, he asserts something incompatible with
(i), but not with (ii) or (iii).
Sellars' account of the practice of using 'looks', in terms of the
withholding of endorsement when one suspects systematic error in one's
responsive dispositions, can account for the difference in scope of endorsement
that (i)-(iii) exhibit. But how could
that difference be accounted for by an approach that understands ‘looks’ talk
as reporting a distinctive kind of particular, about which we are
incorrigible?
Sellars
finds a further confirmation of his account of ‘looks’ talk—and so of the two
factor account of observational capacities that animates it—in its capacity to
explain the possibility of reporting a merely generic (more accurately, merely determinable) look. Thus it is
possible for an apple to look merely red, without its looking any specific
shade of red (crimson, scarlet, etc.).
It is possible for a plane figure to look many-sided without there being
some particular number of sides (say 119) which it looks to have. But if 'looks' statements are to be
understood as reports of the presence before the eye of the mind of a
particular which is (, how can this
possibility be understood? Particulars
are completely determinate. A horse has
a particular number of hairs, though as Sellars points out, it can look to have merely 'a lot' of them. It is a particular shade of brown (or
several shades), even though it may look only darkly colored. So how are such generic, merely
determinable, looks possible? Sellars'
account is in terms of scope of endorsement.
One says that the plane figure looks 'merely many-sided' instead of
'119-sided' just in case one is willing only to endorse (be held responsible
for justifying) the more general claim.
This is a matter of how far one is willing to trust one's responsive
dispositions, a matter of the epistemic credence one feels they deserve or are
able to sustain. Particulars, even if
they are sense contents, cannot be colored without being some determinate color
and shade. How then can the sense datum
theorist—who wants to say that when something looks j to S, something in S is j—account for the fact that something can look colored
without looking to be any particular color, or look red without looking to be
any particular shade of red? So
Sellars' account of 'looks' talk in terms of endorsement can account for two
aspects of that kind of discourse that no theory that invokes a given can
explain: the scope distinctions between qualitative and existential lookings,
and the possibility of merely generic or determinable lookings.
IV. A Rationalist Account of
the Acquisition of Empirical Concepts
It is characteristic of empiricism as Sellars understands (and rejects) it, that it countenances a notion of awareness or experience meeting two conditions. First, it goes beyond mere differential responsiveness in having some sort of cognitive content—that is, content of the sort that under favorable circumstances amounts to knowledge. This is the idea of a notion of awareness or experience of a red triangle in one’s visual field that can at the same time be (or be one’s evidence for) knowledge that there is a red triangle in one’s visual field. Second, this sort of awareness is preconceptual: the capacity to be aware in this sense or have experiences of this sort is prior to and independent of the possession of or capacity to apply concepts. The idea of a kind of awareness with these two features is what Sellars calls the “Myth of the Given.”
Whatever difficulties there may be with such a conception—most notably the incoherences Sellars rehearses in the opening sections of EPM—it does provide the basis for a story about concept acquisition. Concepts are understood as acquired by a process of abstraction, whose raw materials are provided by exercises of the primitive capacity for immediate, preconceptual awareness.[9] One may—and Sellars does—raise questions about whether it is possible to elaborate this story in a coherent fashion. But one ought also to ask the corresponding question to the empricists’ rationalist opponents. Rationalists like Sellars claim that all awareness is a conceptual affair. Being aware of something, in any sense that goes beyond mere responsiveness in its potential cognitive significance—paradigmatically in its capacity to serve as evidence—is bringing it under a concept. Sense experience cannot be the basis for the acquisition of concepts, since it presupposes the capacity to apply concepts. So how do knowers acquire concepts? At this point in the dialectic, classical rationalists such as Leibniz threw up their hands and invoked innate ideas—denying that at least the most basic and general concepts were acquired at all. Sellars owes either a defense of innatism, or an alternative account of concept acquisition.
Sellars rejects innatism. Grasp of a concept is mastery of the use of a word, so concepts are acquired in the process of learning a language. But if we don’t acquire the concept green by noticing green things, since we must already have the concept in order to notice green things as such (by applying the concept to them), how is it possible for us to learn the use of the word ‘green’, and hence acquire the concept? We each start by learning the corresponding RDRDs: being trained to respond to visibly green things by uttering what is still for the novice just the noise ‘green’. This much, the parrot can share. Besides these language-entry moves, the language learner must also master the inferential moves in the vicinity of ‘green’: that the move to ‘colored’ is OK, and the move to ‘red’ is not, and so on. Training in these basic language-language moves consists in acquiring more RDRDs, only now the stimuli, as well as the responses, are utterances.
If a two year old wobbles into the living room and utters the sentence “The house is on fire,” we will not generally take him to have claimed or expressed the belief that the house is on fire. He does not know what he is saying—in the sense that he does not yet know what he would be committing herself to by that claim, or what would be evidence for it or against it. If a five year old child utters the same sentence, though, we may well take the utterance to have the significance of a claim, the expression of a belief. We take it to be the adoption of a stance in the dimension of endorsement, to be the undertaking of a commitment, by holding the child responsible for her claim: asking for her evidence, asking her what she thinks we should to about it, and so on. For it is now presumed that she can tell what she is committing herself to, and what would entitle her to that commitment, and so knows what she is saying, what claim she is endorsing, what belief she is expressing. When the child masters enough of the inferential moves in the vicinity of a responsively elicited utterance of “That is red,” she is taken to have endorsed a claim, and so to have applied a concept.
On the inferential account of distinctively conceptual articulation, grasping a concept requires mastering the inferential connections between the appropriate use of some words and the appropriate use of others. So on this account there is no such thing as grasping just one concept: grasping any concept requires grasping many concepts. Light dawns slowly over the whole.
How good must one be at discriminating the appropriate antecedents and consequents of using a word in order to count as grasping the concept it expresses? Sellars does not explicitly address this question in EPM, but I think his view is that whether or not one’s utterance has the significance of endorsing a claim, and so of applying a concept, is a question of how it is treated by the other members of the linguistic community. The normative status of committing oneself—taking up a position in the dimension of endorsement—is a social status. One must be good enough at anticipating and fulfilling one’s responsibilities in order to be held responsible, and so for one’s remarks to be accorded authority, in the sense of being treated as providing suitable premises for inferences by others. How much is enough is not a metaphysical matter of recognizing the crossing of some antecedently specifiable boundary, but a social matter of deciding when to recognize a performance as authoritative and hold the performer responsible. It is a question that belongs in a box with when writing one’s name at the bottom of a piece of paper counts as committing oneself to pay the bank a certain sum of money every month for thirty years. Some seventeen year olds may actually understand what they would be committing themselves to better than some twenty two year olds. But the community is not therefore making a metaphysical mistake in treating the latter but not the former as able genuinely to commit themselves.
Sellars account of concept acquisition starts with reliable differential responsive dispositions to respond to environing stimuli by uttering sentences. What is then required is that one’s utterance come to have the significance of making a move in the game of giving and asking for reasons. That requires two elements: the practical inferential know-how required to find one’s way about in the inferential network connecting different sentences, and the social acknowledgment of that know-how as sufficient for one’s performances to have the significance in the linguistic community of commitments to or endorsements of the inferentially articulated claims expressed by those sentences. This story is structured and motivated by Sellars’ two-pronged account of observation reports, as non-inferentially elicited endorsements of inferentially articulated claims.
V. Giving Theoretical Concepts
an Observational Use
As
a final example of the work Sellars calls on his two pronged analysis of
observational capacities to do in "Empiricism and the Philosophy of
Mind", we might consider his account of how theoretical concepts can
acquire an observational use. His
reason for addressing the issue is that he wants to make intelligible the idea
that some sorts of paradigmatic mental occurrences—thoughts and sense
impressions—might first become available to us purely theoretically, and only
later come to be observable by us. For
showing that such a development in our capacities is intelligible provides a means of confounding the cartesian idea
of immediate (that is, noninferential) observability as essential to the very idea of mental occurrences. But my concern here is with the general
point, rather than this particular application of it.
The
first point to realize is that, as I mentioned above, according to Sellars’
view, the distinction between theoretical objects and observable objects is methodological, rather than ontological. That is, theoretical and observable objects are not different
kinds of thing. They differ only in how
we come to know about them. Theoretical
objects are ones of which we can only have inferential
knowledge, while observable objects can also be known noninferentially. Theoretical concepts are ones we can only be
entitled to apply as the conclusions of inferences, while concepts of
observables also have noninferential uses.
But the line between things to which we have only inferential cognitive
access and things to which we also have noninferential cognitive access can
shift with time, for instance as new instruments are developed. Thus when first postulated to explain
perturbations in the orbit of Neptune, Pluto was a purely theoretical
object; the only claims we could make
about it were the conclusions of inferences.
But the development of more powerful telescopes eventually made it
accessible to observation, and so a subject of noninferential reports. Pluto did not then undergo an ontological
change. All that changed was its
relation to us.[10]
It
might be objected to this view that when the issue of the ontological status of
theoretical entities is raised, they are not considered merely as objects in
principle like any others save that they happen at the moment to be beyond our
powers of observation. They are thought
of as unobservable in a much stronger
sense: permanently and in principle inaccessible to observation. But Sellars denies that anything is
unobservable in this sense. To be
observable is just to be noninferentially reportable. Noninferential reportability requires only that there are circumstances
in which reporters can apply the concepts in question (the dimension of
inferentially articulated endorsement) by exercising reliable differential
dispositions to respond to the objects in question (the causal dimension), and
know that they are doing so. In this
sense, physicists with the right training can noninferentially report the presence of mu mesons in cloud
chambers. In this sense of
‘observation’, nothing real is in principle beyond the reach of
observation. (Indeed, in Sellars’
sense, one who mastered reliable differential responsive dispositions
noninferentially to apply normative
vocabulary would be directly observing normative facts. It is in this sense that we might be said to
be able to hear, not just the noises
someone else makes, but their words,
and indeed, what they are saying—their
meanings.) It is an empirical question what circumstances we can come
reliably to respond to differentially.
The development of each new sort of measuring instrument potentially
expands the realm of the here-and-now observable.
Once
one sees that observation is not based on some primitive sort of preconceptual
awareness, the fact that some observation reports are riskier than others and
that when challenged we sometimes retreat to safer ones from which the
originals can be inferred will not tempt one to think that the original reports
were in fact the products of inference from those basic or minimal
observations. The physicist, if
challenged to back up his report of a mu-meson may indeed justify his claim by
citing the distinctively hooked vapor trail in the cloud chamber. This is something else observable, from
which the presence of the mu meson can, in the right circumstances, be
inferred. But to say that is not to say
that the original report was the product of an inference after all. It was the exercise of a reliable
differential responsive disposition keyed to a whole chain of reliably
covarying events, which includes mu mesons, hooked vapor trails, and retinal
images. What makes it a report of mu
mesons, and not of hooked vapor trails or retinal images is the inferential
role of the concept the physicist noninferentially applies. (It is a consequence of something’s being a
mu meson, for instance, that it is much
smaller than a finger, which does not
follow from something’s being a hooked vapor trail.) If mu meson is the
concept the physicist applies noninferentially, then if he is sufficiently
reliable, when correct, that is what he sees. His retreat, when a question is raised, to a
report of a hooked vapor trail, whose presence provides good inferential reason
for the original, noninferentially elicited claim, is a retreat to a report
that is safer in the sense that he is a more
reliable reporter of hooked vapor trails than of mu mesons, and that it takes
less training to be able reliably to report vapor trails of a certain shape, so
that is a skill shared more widely. But
the fact that an inferential justification can be offered, and that the demand
for one may be in order, no more undermines the status of the original report
as noninferentially elicited (as genuinely an observation) than does the
corresponding fact that I may under various circumstances be obliged to back up
my report of something as red by invoking my reliability as a reporter of red
things in these circumstances—from which, together with my disposition to call
it red, the claim originally endorsed noninferentially may be inferred.
Thus
one can start with grasp of a concept that consists entirely in mastery of its
use as a premise and conclusion in inferences—that is, as a purely theoretical
concept—and by the addition of suitable RDRDs come to be able to use them
observationally, perhaps in observations whose standard conditions include not
only such items as good light (as in the tie shop case) but also the presence
of various sorts of instruments. This
argument once again appeals to and depends upon Sellars’ understanding of
observational capacities as the product of reliable noninferential responsive
dispositions and mastery of inferential norms.
VI. Conclusion: On the Relation
Between the Two Components
Sellars’ primary explanatory target in "Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind" is our knowledge of the current contents of our own minds. He wants to rethink our understanding of the way in which we experience or are aware of what we are thinking and how things perceptually seem to us. The point I have been trying to make in this essay is that the master idea that guides his argument is a particular way of thinking, not about our knowledge of the contents of our own minds, but about our observational knowledge of ordinary empirical states of affairs. It is because he understands perceptual awareness of a red apple in front of one as he does that Sellars rejects a host of traditional ways of thinking about awareness of having a sense impression of a red apple or the thought that there is a red apple in front of one.
I have claimed Sellars understands the sort of perceptual awareness of external objects that is expressed in observation reports as the product of exercising two different sorts of capacities: the capacity reliably to respond differentially to stimuli (which we share both with merely sentient creatures such as parrots and with merely irritable devices such as thermostats and landmines) and the capacity to take up positions and make moves in a game of giving and asking for reasons. I have rehearsed the way I see some of the major arguments and conceptual moves in the essay as rooted in this two ply conception: the account of the use of ‘looks’ talk that underlies the incorrigibility of sincere contemporaneous first-person reports of how things perceptually seem to one, including the treatment of scoped and generic ‘looks’ claims, Sellars’ approach to the issue of concept acquisition, which caused so much trouble for traditional rationalists, and his rendering of the distinction between theoretical and observational concepts.
I would like to close with some observations and questions about the relations between the two kinds of ability whose cooperation Sellars sees as required for observation. The two sorts of capacities define dimensions of perceptual awareness that are in a certain sense orthogonal. We saw in the discussion of concept acquisition the broad outlines of a story about how one might move from possession of mere RDRDs to the capacity to apply observational concepts. And we saw in the discussion of theoretical and observational concepts how one might move from the purely inferential capacity to apply a concept, by the addition of suitable RDRDs, to mastery of a fully observational concept. That is, we saw in the case of particular observational concepts how one could have either of the two components without the other, and then move to having both.
But this shows only local independence of the two components: that one can have the RDRD of an observational concept without having the concept, and one can have a concept without having the RDRD needed to be able to apply it observationally. The corresponding global independence claim is not true. Purely theoretical concepts do not form an autonomous language game, a game one could play though one played no other. For one must be able to respond conceptually to the utterances of others in order to be talking at all. So one could not play the game of giving and asking for reasons at all unless one could apply at least some concepts noninferentially, in the making of observation reports. But this does not mean that there could not be an insulated region of purely theoretical concepts, say those of pure mathematics—‘insulated’ in the sense that they had no inferential connection to anything inferentially connected to a concept that had an observational use. I don’t say that any actual mathematics is like this, though it may be. Pure mathematics, I think, is in principle applicable to ordinary empirical objects, both those accessible through observation and those (now) accessible only inferentially. Applying an abstract mathematical structure to concrete objects is using the former to guide our inferences concerning the latter. But this relation ought not to be assimilated to that between theoretical objects and observable objects. It is not clearly incompatible with a kind of inferential insulation of the game of giving and asking for reasons concerning the mathematical structures. I think there are many interesting issues in the vicinity that are as yet not fully explored.[11]
It might seem that there could be no interesting question concerning the potential independence of RDRDs, corresponding to this question about the potential independence of the game of giving and asking for reasons. For it seems obvious that there can be reliable differential responsive dispositions without conceptual capacities. That is what mere sentients and artifacts have. But I think in fact there is a subtle question here, and I want to end by posing it. To begin with, what is obvious is at most that the RDRD’s corresponding to some observational concepts can be exhibited by creatures who lack the corresponding concepts. And we might doubt even this. The story of John in the tie shop reminds us that our dispositions actually to call things red can be quite complex, and interact with our background beliefs—for instance about what are standard conditions for observing red things, and what conditions we are in—in complex ways. Though this claim goes beyond what Sellars’ says, I think that learning about systematic sources of error can lead us to alter not just how we express our dispositions (substituting ‘looks j’ for ‘is j’), but eventually even those dispositions themselves. I think, though I cannot say that I am sure (a condition that itself ought to give some sorts of cartesians pause), that familiarity with the Müller-Lyer illusion has brought me to a state in which one of the lines no longer even looks to me to be longer than the other. The more theoretically laden our concept of standard conditions for some sort of observation are (think of the mu-meson case, where those conditions involve the presence of a cloud chamber), the less likely it is that a creature who could deploy no concepts whatsoever could master the RDRDs of a sophisticated observer.
Besides creatures who lack concepts entirely (because they are not players in any game of giving and asking for reasons), we could ask about which RDRDs are in principle masterable by concept users who for some reason lack the specific concepts that for the genuine observer are keyed to the RDRDs in question. It might be, for all I know, that by suitable reinforcement I could be trained to sort potsherds into two piles, which I label with the nonsense terms ‘ping’ and ‘pong’, in such a way that I always and only put Toltec potsherds in the ‘ping’ pile, and Aztec ones in the ‘pong’ pile. What would make my noises nonsense is that they do not engage inferentially with my use of any other expressions. And we might suppose that I do not have the concepts Toltec and Aztec. If told to substitute the labels ‘Toltec’ and ‘Aztec’ for ‘ping’ and ‘pong’, I would then be a kind of idiot savant with respect to the noninferential applicability of those concepts (which I would still not grasp). Perhaps there are no conceptual limits to such idiot savantry. But I find it hard to conceive of cases in which someone who lacks all the relevant concepts nonetheless can acquire the RDRDs necessary to serve as a measuring device (not, by hypothesis, a genuine reporter) of observable instances of the applicability of thick moral concepts such as courage, sensitivity, cruelty, justice, and so on. Of course, unless one endorses something like Sellars’ account of what is required for something to be observable, it will seem that such properties are not suitable candidates for being observable by anybody, never mind by idiot savants. But for those of us who do accept his approach, this sort of question is one that must, I think, be taken seriously. That is the thought I want to leave you with.
References
[Sellars 1956]: Wilfrid Sellars, Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind with an Introduction by Richard Rorty and a Study Guide by Robert Brandom [Harvard University Press, 1997]. Original publication in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 1, ed. Herbert Feigl and Michael Scriven [University of Minnesota Press, 1956].
[1] I tell this story in a great deal more detail in Tales of the Mighty Dead, forthcoming from Harvard University Press, in which a version of this essay also appears.
[2] I would call it ‘minimal empiricism’, except that John McDowell (in the Introduction to the paperback edition of Mind and World [Harvard University Press, 1996) has adopted that term for a much more committal thesis.
[3] Phenomenology, paragraph 109 (in numeration of A.V. Miller’s translation [Oxford University Press, 1979]).
[4] They would not be so characterizable in cases where the response is specified in, say, normative or semantic vocabulary—for instance, as correctly using the word ‘red’, or as applying the concept red.
[5] Sellars discussion begins at [EPM16]. All references are to section numbers of Sellars’ "Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind", reprinted with an Introduction by Richard Rorty and a Study Guide by Robert Brandom [Harvard University Press, 1997].
[6] See for instance [EPM36].
[7] The idiom of “language-language” moves and “language-entry” moves is drawn from Sellars’ “Some Reflections on Language Games” (in Science, Perception, and Reality [London: Routledge, Kegan Paul, 1963]).
[8] I might be mistaken about whether red is what it looks, that is, whether the property expressed by the word ‘red’ is the one it looks to have. But that, the thought goes, is another matter. I cannot be mistaken that it looks that way, like that, where this latter phrase is understood as having a noncomparative use. It looks-red, a distinctive phenomenal property, which we may inconveniently only happen to be able to pick out by its association with a word for a real-world property.
[9] It is tempting to think that on this line concepts are related to the contents of preconceptual experiences as universals to particulars. But as Sellars points out, the empiricists in fact took as primitive the capacity to be aware of already of repeatables, such as redness and squareness. This might suggest that the relation is better understood as one of genus to species. But scarlet is not strictly a species of the genus red, since there need be no way to specify the relevant differentiae without mentioning the species. (Compare the relation between the phenomenal property of redness and that of being colored.) So the relation between immediately experienceable contents and the concepts under which they are classified is better understood as that of determinate repeatable to determinables under which it falls.
[10] Notice that this realism about theoretical entities does not entail scientific realism in the sense that privileges science over other sorts of cognitive activity, although Sellars usually discusses the two sorts of claims together.
[11] See for instance McDowell’s discussion in “Brandom on Inference and Representation,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LVII, No.1, March 1997, pp. 157ff, and my reply at pp. 189ff, and a paper by John MacFarlane entitled "McDowell's Kantianism" forthcoming in a volume devoted to McDowell's work.