CONTENT, CHARACTER AND COLOR I:
AGAINST STANDARD REPRESENTATIONALISM
[This material is slightly revised and reorganized from two Whitehead lectures given at Harvard in April 2002. The first NEH presentation (this file) corresponds to the first Whitehead lecture and the beginning of the second. The second NEH presentation corresponds to the rest of the second lecture, plus “Introspection and Phenomenal Character”.]
The
words “content” and “character” in my title refer to the representational
content and phenomenal character of color experiences. So my topic concerns the nature of our
experience of color. But I will, of course,
be talking about colors as well as color experience.
Let
me set the stage by mentioning some things, some more controversial than
others, that I will be taking for granted.
I assume, to begin with, that objects in the world have colors, and have
them independently of being perceived to have them, and independently even of there
being creatures capable of perceiving them.
I think, and this of course sets me apart from the many color irrealists
among philosophers and color scientists, that any reasonable semantics for
color terms, and any reasonable account of the reference of color concepts,
should yield the result that colors are
properties of external things that are realized in certain of their physical
properties, namely those responsible for their reflecting or emitting the light
whose impact on our retinas is involved in causing our color perceptions.
This
brings me to a further assumption that I shall be making, namely the truth of
physicalism. I take physicalism to be
the thesis that all properties of things either are or are realized in basic
physical properties, where basic physical properties are the properties that
underlie the behavior and causal powers of inanimate things. There are two ways in which the commitment
to physicalism will figure in my discussion.
First, I assume that colors are physically realized properties. Second, I assume that color experiences are
physically realized. These two
commitments frame the problem I am discussing – how can colors be properties
realized in the microphysical properties of things, and how can color
experience be so realized?
I
don’t think there is any generally accepted account of what it is for a
property to be “realized in” other properties.
For those who think, as I do, that properties are individuated by their
causal features, it should seem plausible to say that property P realizes
property Q just in case the forward looking causal features of Q are a subset
of the forward looking causal features of P, and the backward looking causal
features of P are a subset of the backward looking causal features of Q.[1] Taking the relation of determinates to
determinables to be a special case of the realization relation, we can
illustrate this with red and scarlet – the forward looking causal features of
red, i.e., the contributions it can make to causing various effects, are a
subset of those of scarlet, and the backward looking causal features of
scarlet, i.e., its being such that its instantiation can be caused in certain
ways, are a subset of the backward looking causal features of red.
I
think the view that colors, insofar as they are properties of material things,
are physically realized is one that has been widely accepted even by
philosophers who would emphatically reject the view that any mental
properties are physically realized. It
is a view Descartes clearly accepted, although in some passages his view about
color sounds more like eliminativism than physicalism. The view that colors are properties of
material things, but properties of them that
are caused by, rather than realized in, their microphysical
properties, is incompatible with what we know about the role of the
microphysical properties in causing our experiences of color.
That
color experiences are realized in the physical, presumably in physical states
of our brains, is of course much more controversial. This is not something I shall argue for. It figures here as a widely accepted
assumption that for those who hold it poses part of the puzzle about color and
color experience. This is a special
case of a puzzle that has figured centrally in recent discussions in the
philosophy of mind – for example, Thomas Nagel’s discussion of “what it is
like” to be in conscious mental states, and Frank Jackson’s example of the
black and white room bound physiologist who knows all of the physical facts
about color perception but does not know what it is like to see red. Appropriating Joseph Levine’s term
“explanatory gap,” I will refer to this problem as the subjective
explanatory gap.[2] It is, in brief, the problem of how, given
what it is like to be in subjective mental states, these states can be realized
in physical states of our brains.
Nowhere does this problem arise more vividly than in the case of color
experience.
But
there is also an objective explanatory gap problem, which is in some
ways more fundamental and certainly of
much greater antiquity. This is the
problem of how colors, given their perceived nature, can be, or be realized in,
physical properties of things, given what we know about these physical properties. This is a central case of the problem
Wilfrid Sellars raised by asking how, if at all, we can reconcile the “manifest
image,” embodied in the common sense view of the world and our ordinary
experience of it, with the “scientific image.”[3] And it is a problem that clearly exercised
presocratic Greek atomists like Democritus and seventeenth century thinkers
such as Galileo, Descartes, and Locke.
A
time-honored response to this problem, found in all of the thinkers just
mentioned, is that of “kicking upstairs into the mind” the phenomenal or
qualitative character we confront in our perception of color. The idea is that what we naturally think of
as the perceived nature of the color is really the nature of the experience
produced in us by the object perceived as having the color. Sometimes, as in Democritus and Galileo, and
in recent theorists such as Paul Boghossian and David Velleman, this takes an
eliminativist form.[4] Strictly speaking, external objects don’t
have colors, and our perception of them as colored is an illusion – perhaps
involving the projection onto them of features of our experiences. Sometimes it takes the form of a
dispositional theory of color, according to which an object’s having a certain
color is simply a disposition, or in Lockean terms a “power,” to produce experiences
of a certain sort in perceivers under certain conditions. And sometimes it takes the form of a view
that allows that colors are objective and nondispositional properties of
external things, but holds that the phenomenal character of our experiences of
colors is only contingently related to what colors they represent, so that in
principle different observers, with different sorts of perceptual systems,
could perceive the same colors by means of phenomenally very different
experiences, and could perceive different colors by having phenomenally
identical experiences.
If
by “intersubjective spectrum inversion” one means a situation in which two different observers differ in the way just
described in how the phenomenal character of their color experiences relates to
the colors of things, and yet both veridically perceive the colors of things,
then it is only the last of these views that is committed to the possibility of
such spectrum inversion. The eliminativist
view denies that there is any veridical perception of the colors of things,
while a dispositionalist view that individuates the colors by the phenomenal
character of the experiences they produce cannot allow that the same color is
veridically perceived via phenomenally different experiences. But in a broader sense, all of these views
allow the possibility of intersubjective spectrum inversion. All hold that the relation between the
phenomenal character of color experiences and the intrinsic nature of perceived
objects is contingent in a way that allows different subjects to differ
systematically in the phenomenal character of their experiences of objects of a
certain intrinsic nature without these subjects differing with respect to the
veridicality of their experiences.
As
has often been observed, employing the strategy of solving the objective
explanatory gap problem by “kicking the phenomenal character upstairs” can
seem, when done by physicalists, to be a case of moving the bump in the rug
from one place to another. A dualist
like Descartes can construe this as kicking the phenomenal character into the
nonphysical realm of the mind; but for the physicalist there is no such
nonphysical realm. The experiences
having the phenomenal character will itself
have to be physically realized. And this of course poses what I have called the subjective
explanatory gap problem. It can seem
that we have just traded one explanatory gap problem for another.
The
subjective explanatory gap problem has to do with the phenomenal character of
perceptual experiences. Discussion of
this has been transformed in the last decade or two by the widespread
acceptance of what has come to be called the “transparency” of perceptual
experiences. The classical expression
of this is G.E. Moore’s observation in “The Refutation of Idealism,” published
almost a century ago, that the sensation of blue is as if it were diaphanous;
if one tries to introspect it one sees right through to the blue.[5] This has been seen by many as showing that
it is a mistake to suppose that the perception of colors involves the
possession by perceptual experiences of “qualia” or “sensational properties”
that give them their phenomenal character, i.e., determine “what it is like” to
have them. Treating this as a mistake
goes with a certain sort of “representationalist” view about the phenomenal
character of perceptual experiences, one that says that the phenomenal
character of a color experience simply consists in its representing, its being
“of,” a certain array of colors in the scene being viewed. I will call this “standard
representationalism,” to distinguish it from a different version of
representationalism I will be defending later on. Standard representationalism has been held by a number of recent
writers, including Gilbert Harman, Bill Lycan, Michael Tye, Fred Dretske, Alex
Byrne, and David Hilbert.[6] In his paper “A Simple View of Color” John
Campbell gives a vivid expression of an apparent consequence of this view when
he writes that “the qualitative character of a colour-experience is inherited
from the qualitative character of the color.”[7] The wording here might suggest a resemblance
theory, according to which color experiences resemble the colors of things, but
I take it that Campbell’s view is rather that the experiences “inherit” their
qualitative character from the colors just in the sense that their having the
qualitative character they do is simply a matter of their representing,
perceptually, the qualitative character of the colors.
Standard
representationalism has no room for the possibility of spectrum inversion,
unless the inversion is taken to involve systematic misperception on the part
of one of the invertees. Given that it
identifies the phenomenal character of a color experience with that aspect of
its representational content that has to do with its representation of color,
it cannot allow that the phenomenal character of such experiences and their
color content can vary independently of one another.
It
can easily seem that standard representationalism provides a quick solution to
the subjective explanatory gap problem.
The problem of how physical states of the brain, or states realized in
these, can have representational content is widely regarded as a tractable one. There are causal-correlational accounts, teleological
accounts, and cognitive role accounts that are compatible with physicalism, and
while none of these commands universal assent it is widely thought that
something along one or more of these lines must be right. If so, and if the phenomenal character
of perceptual experiences is just a special sort of representational content,
there is an explanation in the offing of how it can be physically realized.
I
said that the time-honored response to the objective explanatory gap problem
involves kicking the phenomenal or qualitative character of color upstairs into
the mind. One could likewise say that
standard representationalism solves the subjective explanatory gap problem by
kicking the phenomenal character downstairs, into the external
world. But if moving the bump in the
rug into the mind does not get rid of it, neither does moving it in the
opposite direction. For now we have the
objective explanatory gap problem back again.
How can color as we perceive it be a micro-physically realized
property? How can it be such a property
that our experiences of color represent?
And about this proponents of standard representationalism seem to me to
be, for the most part, in a state of denial.
This
sets the stage for the rest of what I will be saying in these lectures. I think that the Moorean “transparency”
claim is, property understood, correct.
And as I have already mentioned, I accept a version of
representationalism about phenomenal character. This is a view according to which the phenomenal character of
color experiences consists in an aspect of their representational content, but
according to which the properties represented in this part of their content are
not the colors but other properties closely related to them. This view will be presented in my second
lecture. In the remainder of the
present lecture I will be explaining why I think that standard
representationalism is mistaken. As I
have already indicated, I take standard representationalism to deny the
possibility of spectrum inversion, except on an understanding of it on which
anyone whose color experience was inverted relative to that of a veridical
perceiver of the colors would have to be systematically misperceiving the
colors. So among other things, I will
be arguing that an acceptable account of color perception must allow the
possibility of spectrum inversion without systematic misperception. I will postpone till my next lecture a
consideration of the question of where this leaves the two explanatory gap
problems I have distinguished.
There
are a number of considerations that seem to show that in some sense the
ways things appear to us with respect to color are partly a function of the
nature of our perceptual system, and so pose a problem for standard
representationalism and for the idea that our experiences simply inherit their
qualitative character from the colors they represent. First of all, there is the enormous variety of the physical bases
of what we perceive as a single color.
Many different mixtures of lights of different wavelengths are metamers,
meaning that they produce indistinguishable color experiences in human
subjects. Surface color is realized in
properties called surface spectral reflectances, or just reflectances, each of
which is specified by saying what percentage of the light of each wavelength
that surface reflects. And under normal
lighting conditions, vast numbers of different reflectances will be
indistinguishable by ordinary perceivers and perceived as the same color. Moreover, for each reflectance there are a
vast number of physically very different microphysical properties that will
realize it, i.e., will confer the set of light-reflecting dispositions that
define it. So each determinate shade of
color is realized in a number of different reflectances, each of which in turn
is realized in a vast number of microphysical properties. And of course not all colors are surface
colors. The blue we see on some
surfaces is realized in yet other ways in transparent glass bottles, in neon
lights, in lakes and oceans, and in the sky.
Where
is the qualitative character that all of these realizers of a particular shade
of color share, and is inherited by our experience of that shade? If we ask why it is that things having these
different properties look alike with respect to color, the answer will come in
part from the part of physics that deals with the reflection, absorption, and
emission of light. But when we ask why
the different metamers look alike, the answer lies in part in the nature of our
perceptual apparatus. It is a system so
constructed that for each of a large number of different inputs there is a
single conscious response. And it is so
constructed that the various stimuli that impact on it form what Quine called a
“quality space” – where the similarity ordering constituting such a quality
space is always relative to a certain sort of perceptual system.
A
further point is that there is a structure to the phenomenal character of color
experiences that seems to have no counterpart in their physical realizers, and
has its explanation in the nature of the mechanisms by which we perceive
color. There is a phenomenal
distinction between the “unique hues” – unique red, unique yellow, unique
green, and unique blue – and the “binary hues”, such as orange and purple and
chartreuse. Nothing in a particular
combination of wavelengths, or in the physical properties that account for the
reflection or emission of light with that combination of wavelengths, provides a
clue as to whether the reception of light with that combination of wavelengths
will produce an experience of a unique hue.
Or rather, none of this will provide such a clue until we combine
it with information about the constitution of our opponent processing visual
system. It is the nature of this system
that accounts for what combinations of wavelengths, and what reflectances, are
perceived as unique hues.[8]
What
I have been saying points to an aspect of the objective explanatory gap problem
that has no counterpart in the subjective explanatory gap problem. An important part of explaining phenomenal
character is explaining similarity, including identity, of
phenomenal character. And, as we have
seen, a central part of the objective explanatory gap problem is explaining how
it is that what are physically very diverse properties can be realizers of the
same shade of color, and, more generally, how it is that physical properties
can have a similarity ordering, qua color realizers, that bears no apparent relation to any similarity
relations that would seem salient to someone who was taxonomizing them simply
as physical properties. It is hard to
imagine a plausible explanation of this that is not “subjectivist” to the
extent that it takes the similarity ordering of color realizers as determined by
a similarity ordering of the experiences they produce under certain conditions.
In the case of the
experiences of color there is not the same problem of accounting for the
similarity ordering. It is may well be
that the physical states that are candidates for realizing color experiences
would not seem, considered just as physical states, to have a similarity
ordering that corresponds to the phenomenal similarity ordering of the
experiences they realize. But the very
considerations that would qualify them for being realizers of color experiences
would serve as a basis for such an ordering.
For physical states to count as realizers of color experiences they
would have to play the functional role of experiences vis a vis mediating
connections between sensory stimuli and behavior, including of course the
effect on the subject’s perceptual beliefs.
This means, for example, that ones realizing phenomenally different
experiences would have to be so related that under certain circumstances their
simultaneous or successive occurrence would play a role in producing the
behavior that shows that the subject can discriminate between the stimuli that
produce them, while ones realizing phenomenally very similar experiences would
have to be so related that their occurrence would have a correspondingly
different behavioral effect. Likewise,
ones realizing phenomenally similar or identical experiences would have to be
so related that when one is followed by the other after an interval there would
be, under certain circumstances, the behavioral manifestations of
recognition. And what similarity and
difference relations hold among experiences would have to play a role in the
fixation of belief, both beliefs about the environment and beliefs about the
experiences themselves.
It seems clear that an
account of what makes different physical properties realizers of the same or
similar colors has to bring in their aptness to produce phenomenally identical
or similar color experiences. Is there
a comparable way in which an account of
what makes different neurophysiological states realizers of phenomenally
identical or similar color experiences has to bring in the identity or
similarity of colors? Well, if
phenomenal similarity of color experiences is what we might call intentional
similarity, similarity in representational content, and if the relevant content
has to do with color, then of course it is a requirement on neurophysiological
states realizing phenomenally identical or similar color experiences that they
realize experiences that represent the same or similar colors. But that doesn’t mean that we have to
settle what physical relations count as sameness or similarity of color before
we can settle what counts as sameness or similarity of color experiences. Suppose that we are investigating the color
perception of bees, and undertake the job of discovering two things – what
physical properties realize the colors bees see, and what states of bees
realize experiences of bee color. Plainly
the first thing we would have to do is find out what kinds of discriminatory
and recognitional capacities bees have.
That involves, in the first instance, finding what things look
similar and different with respect to color to bees – i.e., what features of
things are responsible for the light that elicits certain sorts of
discriminatory and recognitional behavior in them. If we take it as criterial of bee-color similarity that,
normally, things that look color-similar to bees are similar in
bee-color, this will give us a way of identifying what things in the world
stand in the relations of bee-color similarity and bee-color difference, which
in turn will give us a way of telling what properties of objects are realizers
of bee-colors. This brings out the
sense in which similarity of color experience is more basic than similarity of
color.
But
there is a version of standard representationalism that holds promise of being
able to acknowledge a kind of dependence of the phenomenal character of color experience on the perceptual system of
the perceiver, while holding that the colors perceived are mind independent and
that the phenomenal character of the experiences just consists in their
representing these properties. This is
a version of what David Hilbert has called “anthropocentric realism,” and of
the view suggested by the title, as well as the contents, of Allan Gibbard’s
recent paper “Visible Properties of Human Interest Only.”[9]
This view does not hold that colors, color similarities, and the perceived
nature of the colors are in any sense the product of our perceptual
system. Rather, it holds that our
perceptual system selects certain properties of external things and
certain relations between them to be the colors and the relations of color
similarity. What determines what
properties and relations are selected is the quality space of the subject,
i.e., what color stimuli are indistinguishable by the subject, what relations
of relative similarity and difference are perceived between objects, and so
forth. In the words of David Hilbert
and Mark Kalderon, who propose such a view in a recent paper, “a pre-existing relation only counts
as similarity in hue, saturation or brightness in virtue of an antecedent
classificatory function of the visual system.
Facts about visual experience fix which of the similarities among
objective properties count as similarities with respect to color.”[10] This is presented as a version of standard
representationalism that denies the possibility of spectrum inversion.
Let
me say how I understand the idea that our visual system “selects” relations to
be relations of color similarity. Here
it helps to remember that there is a sense in which similarity is cheap. For any ordered set of properties we can
define a similarity relation such that the degree of similarity of two
properties in the set is determined by how close they are to each other in that
ordering. Perhaps most of these should
count only as relations of “quasi-similarity.”
But what determines which of these relations count as “real” or
“genuine” similarity relations? A first
step towards an answer is to say that such a relation is a genuine similarity
relation if it makes properties similar to the extent that their instantiation
bestows similar causal powers. But what
sorts of causal powers are relevant will vary depending on our interests. In the case of sensible properties of
things, the relevant powers include the powers to affect the experiences of
perceivers; and in the case of the so-called “secondary qualities” these are
close to being the only powers that are relevant. Powers to affect experiences will be grounded in powers to affect
the physical states of perceptual systems.
And given that a perceptual system realizes a repertoire of perceptual
experiences standing in certain similarity relations, there is an obvious sense
in which its physical nature determines what properties bestow the powers to
produce in the possessor of the system experiences belonging to that
repertoire, and what relations among these properties bestow similarities with
respect to these powers. In this sense
the nature of the perceptual system “selects” what properties are to count as
sensible properties, and what relations among them are to count as similarities
with respect to these properties.
Hilbert
and Kalderon present the selection view as one according to which color content
is Fregean rather than Millian. It is a
natural thought that the Fregean distinction between sense and reference can be
used to explain away the disparity between colors as we experience them and the
surface properties of objects as we know them from science. The idea would be that while a color
experience’s having a certain phenomenal character consists in its having a certain representational content, that
content is to be individuated not just by what color is represented but by the
sense or mode of presentation by which that color is represented. This is
different from any mode of presentation by which the same property might be
represented in the terminology or concepts of physics, and this accounts for
the seeming disparity. Now, the idea
that the phenomenal character of color experiences is determined by modes of
presentation rather than by properties referred to does not seem to square with
the idea that this character is simply “inherited” from the colors
represented. And there is of course a
danger that by making the mode of presentation a feature of the perceptual
experience this view sneaks in by the back door the qualia which standard
representationalism is anxious to reject.
But Hilbert and Kalderon have a view that avoids at least the second of
these worries, and might seem to avoid the first. What partly determines the content of color experiences is their
conceptual role, and this is fixed by their position in the psychological color
space. This serves as the mode of
presentation. So it is the role of the
experiences in perceiving color similarities and differences that partly
determines their contents – and it is this that determines their phenomenal
character. They say that “some
particular aspect of color content is responsible for color phenomenology,” and
they identify that aspect by saying that on their view “the phenomenal
properties of color experiences are identified with the structural constraints
governing them (as determined by their position in the color space.” The same view, that phenomenal character is
relational and determined by position in a psychological quality space, can be
found in Austen Clark’s recent book A Theory of Sentience.[11]
It falls out from the
“selection gambit,” as I will call it, that tetrachromats perceive different
colors than any trichromats, and that trichromats with differently structured
color spaces will perceive different colors.[12] The properties selected to be the colors,
and the relations selected to be the relations of color similarity, can be
different for creatures with different sorts of perceptual systems. So while it will be true on this view that
the phenomenal character of color experiences will be determined in part by the
nature of the subject’s perceptual system, this does not mean that it can vary
independently of the color represented, as in the inverted spectrum
scenario. If different creatures have
phenomenally different color experiences when perceiving the same objects, that
means on the selection view that their experiences represent different
colors. And this doesn’t mean that one
or the other of them is misperceiving; one creature can be veridically perceiving
the object to have a certain color of one sort, say a certain human color,
while another is veridically perceiving the same object to have a certain color
of a different sort, say a certain bee-color.
The same light can carry information about different colors to different
perceptual systems.
It should be noted that as I
am interpreting the selection view, it gives an internalist account of
phenomenal character – for the structure of the color quality space, determined
by a “classificatory function of the visual system,” is an internal matter. This is one of the attractions of the view;
for one thing about which internalism seems intuitively right is the “what it
is like” of perceptual experiences.
Most versions of standard representationalism seem committed to an
externalist account of phenomenal character, and so, assuming physicalism about
color, to the unpalatable view that an experience’s having a certain phenomenal
character consists in its representing some physical property of objects,
leaving us with the mystery of how any of the candidate properties could be
such that its representation confers the phenomenal character we confront in our experience. If the selection gambit can combine
internalism about phenomenal character with standard representationalism, that
will strongly recommend it. I should
mention, however, that despite the passages that support a reading of Hilbert
and Kalderon as internalists about phenomenal character, this reading conflicts
with their official view that the phenomenal character of color experiences is
identical with their representational content.
For this content is not determined by position in the psychological
color space alone, but rather by this together with “the relations normal
subjects bear to their native environment” (p. 301). So on another reading the account of phenomenal character is
partly externalist after all. But to
adopt the view suggested by this reading is to relinquish the chief benefit
promised by the selection view. So I
will stick with the internalist reading suggested by the claim that it is a
“particular aspect” of color content, namely position in the psychological
color space, that determines color phenomenology.
I should emphasize that I
have focused on this view because I think that there is a good deal that is
right in it. The idea that our
perceptual systems “select” objective properties and relations to be colors and
color similarity relations seems to me right; and it seems to be the view that
is needed if we are to reconcile the view that colors are objective properties
of things with the view that similarity of color experiences is more basic than
similarity of color. What I question is
whether this view will serve as a version of standard representationalism. It could do so if we could assume that
perceptual systems having different color quality spaces would always “select”
different properties to be the colors.
But that assumption seems wrong.
It seems possible that the same set of determinate shades of color might
have one similarity ordering relative to one sort of perceptual system, and a
different similarity ordering relative to another. Certainly it seems possible that sets of reflectances should have
different similarity orderings in the experiences of creatures with different
sorts of perceptual systems. Or it
might be that some but not all of the sets of reflectances that are selected as
surface colors by one sort of perceptual system are among those selected as
surface colors by a different sort of perceptual system, so that in the quality
spaces of one of these systems these colors stand in similarity relations to
properties that are not selected as colors at all by the other perceptual
system. It is compatible with this
that within the experience of a given perceiver or kind of perceiver, each color
is picked out by the role it plays in the similarity ordering – so that
positions in this ordering serve as “modes of presentation” of the particular
colors. But suppose that subjects S1
and S2 have differently structured color quality spaces, but that one of S1’s
colors, call it C1, has as surface color realizers the same set of reflectances
as one of S2’s colors, call it C2. More
generally, suppose that C1’s total set of realizers, those for colored lights
and transparent or translucent solids as well as surface colors, is identical
with C2’s total set of realizers.
Nothing in the selection account rules this out, and it seems perfectly
conceivable. If the possible realizers
of C1 are the same as those of C2, it is hard to resist the conclusion that C1
and C2 are the same color. But if they
are the same color, then perceptual systems with differently structured
experiences spaces can “select” the same property in the world as one of the
colors while selecting different similarity relations between it and other
colors. Assuming that this would not
involve systematic misperception on the part of the possessors of one of the
perceptual systems, and there is no reason to think it would, this contradicts
the view of Hilbert and Kalderon that the colors are individuated by their
similarity relations. And if, as they
claim, the phenomenal character of color experiences is determined by what
color similarities they represent, it would seem that it gives us a case in
which veridical experiences of the same color, in the same viewing conditions, differ in phenomenal
character. Given this possibility, it
certainly does not seem that the phenomenal character of color experiences can
be simply inherited from the nature of the colors they represent.
What was just presented was
a case in which creature S1’s experiences representing a certain color differ
phenomenally from creature S2’s experiences of that same color because S1’s and
S2’s visual systems select different similarity relations for that color. Can we also have a case in which S1’s
experiences of color A are phenomenally
like S2’s experiences of a different color B, and S2’s experiences of color A
are phenomenally like S1’s experiences of color B? That is, can we get this sort of spectrum inversion on the
assumption that the visual systems “select” properties and similarity relations
to be colors and color similarity relations.
I think we can.
To show this I need to
introduce a distinction between two sorts of similarity spaces. The color experience space for a
given creature consists in the similarity ordering of the color experience
types belonging to that creature’s repertoire of sensory states. Since any experience of color will at the
same time be an experience of other properties as well, what this is really an
ordering of is a class of representational features of experiences, namely
those involved in the representation of color – I will say something about what
these are in my next lecture. The color
property space for the creature will consist in the similarity ordering of
the properties selected as colors by that creature’s visual system.[13] To a first approximation, there will be an
isomorphism between these – there will be a way of pairing experience types, or
experience features, with properties of objects such that the items in the one
set will stand in a network of similarity relations which is the same as that
the paired items in the other set stand in.
This pairs experience types or features with properties they represent.[14] It is now generally accepted that our
similarity space for colors has an asymmetrical structure.[15] Assuming that a creature’s color experience
space and its color property space have an asymmetrical structure, and of
course the same asymmetrical structure, there will be just one way of pairing
the experiences, or experience features, and properties of objects that yields
such an isomorphism. And the property
represented by an experience of a certain type under normal conditions, and
standardly tracked by it, will occupy the position in the color property space
that corresponds to that occupied by that experience type in the color
experience space. The reason this is
only a first approximation is that the pairing of color experience types with
color properties can vary with viewing conditions. So it would be more accurate to say that there is an isomorphism
of the sort described for each set of viewing conditions. But this is a complication I will allow
myself to ignore.
Now it seems perfectly
possible that two creatures, S1 and S2, should have color property spaces that
are different but nevertheless have the same structure. Their visual systems differ in such a way
that they select somewhat different properties as the colors, and somewhat
different relations as the relations of color similarity and difference. As we might suppose, this is partly because
in some cases what are metamers for one of them are not metamers for the
other. But it might nevertheless be
true that the colors perceived by Sl can be paired with those perceived by S2
in such a way that the similarity relations observed by S1 between things with
his colors are the same as those observed by S2 between things with the
corresponding S2 colors. This of course
requires that the color experience spaces of the two creatures have the same
structure. As we have seen, Hilbert and
Kalderon seem to hold, in common with Austen Clark, that because phenomenal
character is determined by position in a psychological quality space, in such a
case each experience in the repertoire of one of these creatures must be
phenomenally just like its counterpart in the repertoire of the other. I will question that view later on. But while I do not think that each
experience in the repertoire of one of my two creatures would have to be
phenomenally just like its counterpart in the repertoire of the other, I agree
that this could be the case. So
let’s suppose that it is. It also seems
possible that while the two visual systems select different sets of properties,
there is some overlap between the sets they select. That is, some properties are selected by both of them. And we can suppose that in some cases a
property selected by both visual systems occupies a different position in the
color property space of the one than it does in the color property space of the
other. If this is so, then the
experiences of S1 that represent such a
property will have to be phenomenally different from the experiences of S2 that
represent that same property. But if
S2’s experiences with a certain phenomenal character don’t represent the color that S1’s experiences
with that phenomenal character represent, even though that color is one that
both perceive, those experiences of S2 must represent some other color –
and why shouldn’t that also be a color that both of them perceive? If that is possible, it is possible that
there should be two such properties, A and B, such that S1’s experiences of A
are phenomenally just like S2’s experiences of B, and vice versa.
It
may be objected that the claim that color similarities are perceptual system
relative is at odds with things we know a priori to be necessarily true of the
colors, e.g., that orange is more similar to red than it is to green. For aren’t I saying that there might be
perceptual systems such that creatures with those perceptual systems could say,
truly, that orange is more similar to green than to red? Well, no.
They couldn’t say that, truly, and mean by it what those words would
mean coming from my mouth. When I use
those words, the similarity relations I am talking about are those selected by my
sort of perceptual system – and that makes it necessarily true that orange is
more similar to red than to green. Of
course, when the other folk use the same words, the similarity relations they
are talking about are those selected by their sort of perceptual system,
and that makes it true for them to say “Orange is more similar to green than to
red,” where the terms “orange,” “green” and “red” refer to the very same
properties they refer to in my statement.
I
said earlier that if the possible realizers of color C1 are the same as the
possible realizers of color C2, it is hard to resist the conclusion that C1 and
C2 are the same color. And my
subsequent argument has rested on that conclusion. Those who do not like where that argument has taken me may feel
that it is after all not so hard to resist that conclusion.
One way of resisting it is
to be a certain sort of dispositionalist about colors. Let a relational power be one that is
grounded not only in the intrinsic properties of the thing that has it but also
in the existence of a kind of things that in suitable circumstances would be
affected in a certain way by the exercise of the power. Adapting
Robert Boyle’s famous example, the power of a key to open a certain door
will be a relational power if it is one that we can deprive the key of by
changing the lock. If colors were
relational powers, two different colors could be alike in what intrinsic
properties of colored objects they are grounded in, and yet different because
the existence of the powers would involve different sorts of perceivers – one
is a power to produce experiences of one sort in one sort of perceiver, and the
other is a power to produce a different sort of experience in another sort of
perceiver. They would not be
necessarily coextensive, because the existence of perceivers of the one sort
would be independent of the existence of perceivers of the other sort. This view has the cost of implying that
before there were perceivers there were no colors. That seems to me reason enough to reject it.
Could
one maintain instead that colors are intrinsic powers, i.e., powers
grounded only in the intrinsic properties of the things that have them, and
still maintain that two different colors could be alike in what intrinsic
properties ground them, i.e., are their “categorical bases”? It does seem natural to say that the power
to produce experiences of type A in perceivers having one sort of visual system
is a different power than the power to produce experiences of type B in
creatures with a different sort of visual system, even though these are powers
the things have whether or not creatures with those sorts of visual system
exist, are grounded in the same intrinsic properties of their possessors, and
are necessarily coextensive.
But suppose I am presented
with a coin, and told that it has two different intrinsic powers. It gets you a Coke if inserted into the slot
of an Alpha machine, and it gets you a Pepsi if inserted into the slot of a
Beta machine. It might turn out that
Alpha and Beta machines are mechanically identical, the only difference between
them being that Alpha machines are stocked with Coke and Beta machines are stocked
with Pepsi. So the proximate effect of
inserting the coin is the same whether it is inserted in an Alpha machine or in
a Beta machine. Here it seems clear
that in no sense are different intrinsic properties of the coin involved
in producing the Coke output than in producing the Pepsi output. If we have different intrinsic powers
here, these powers are not different intrinsic properties. The difference seems conceptual rather than
ontological – we have a single property in virtue of having which an object
falls under two different dispositional concepts. And it might be like this with colors. Let C1 be a color perceived by an observer with one sort of
perceptual system, and C2 a color perceived by an observer with a different
sort of perceptual system. It might be
that these are grounded in the same intrinsic properties of objects, and that
the proximate effects of the presentation of something with C1 on an observer
of the one sort are the same as the proximate effects of the presentation of something with C2 on an observer of the
other sort, although the experiences eventually produced are
different. If colors are intrinsic properties, C1 and C2
are the same color. We can allow that
an object having this property has two different “intrinsic powers,” these
being powers to affect the two sorts of observers. But these won’t be different colors – they will be, perhaps, the
same color under two different descriptions.
The inverted spectrum
scenario I have described is not the one that has been most frequently
discussed in the literature. The most
frequently discussed case is that in which the inversion is behaviorally
undetectable – the two creatures make all of the same color discriminations,
and apply color words in exactly the same way. That possibility requires that the color experience space and
the color property space have a symmetrical structure. As already mentioned, our color experience
space and color property space do not have a symmetrical structure. This comes out in a variety of ways. One is that there are more discriminable
shades between unique red and unique yellow than there are between unique blue
and unique green – so there is no mapping which both maps unique hues onto
unique hues and preserves the resemblance relations among the hues. Another is the fact that whereas
blackened blues are perceived as blues,
blackened yellows are perceived as a different color, brown; this sort of fact
precludes a mapping that maps color categories onto other color categories of
the same size.[16] All of this seems to preclude the
possibility that there should be creatures who are spectrum inverted relative
to us in a behaviorally undetectable way.
The inversion I have described, which involves visual systems that
differ somewhat in what relations they “select” to be the relations of color
similarity, would of course be behaviorally detectable.
It is nevertheless a
question of some interest whether it is possible for there to be creatures with
symmetrical color quality spaces for whom undetectable spectrum inversion would
be a possibility. A number of writers,
including Daniel Dennett, Austen Clark, and Hilbert and Kalderon, argue that it
is not. Hilbert and Kalderon point out
that given that our own color experience space is asymmetrical, and given that
color experiences are individuated by their similarity and difference relations
to other experiences in the same experience space, none of our color
experiences could be the same as any of the color experiences of the
hypothetical creature with a symmetrical color experience space. They take this to show that we cannot
conceive of the experiences of such a creature in the way we would have to be
able to do in order to conceive of a creature spectrum inverted relative to it. But they argue further that it is
impossible that there should be such an experience space. They think that because the phenomenal
character of experiences is determined by the similarity relations they stand
it, there must be asymmetries in the structure of the space in order for the
phenomenal character of different experiences in it to be different. Here they cite with approval a passage from
Daniel Dennett – directed, as it happens, against me – in which he says that
“what anchors our naive sense that there are such properties as qualia
are the multiple, asymmetrical, interdependent
sets of reactive dispositions by which we acquaint ourselves with the
sensible world,” and that for the
hypothetical creatures with a symmetrical experience space “what it was like to
have one sort of experience would not differ at all from what it was like to
have a different one.”[17]
Let me take up these points
in order. I agree that if there were
creatures with symmetrical color experience spaces, none of their experiences
could be phenomenally the same as any of ours.
And I agree that we would not be able to imagine what it is like to have
their experiences. Does this show that
we could not be in a position to refer to their experiences in a way that would
enable us to describe creatures that are spectrum inverted relative to
them? No, it does not. First of all, no reason has been given why
we could not, by testing the discriminatory and recognitional capacities of
these creatures, map the structure of their color quality space and find that
it indeed has a symmetrical structure.
And we could have good behavioral evidence that certain stimuli always
produce in them, under certain conditions, experiences identical in phenomenal
character. This would give us a way of
fixing the reference of terms designating their kinds of color experience;
e.g., we might fix the reference of the term “red*” with the description “the
phenomenal character of the color experiences they have when viewing ripe
tomatoes in daylight,” and the term “green*” with the description “the phenomenal
character of the color experiences they have when viewing unripe tomatoes in
daylight.” We could then describe the
hypothetical case of creatures who also have a symmetrical color experience
spaces but who get green* experiences from ripe tomatoes and red* experiences
from unripe tomatoes.
I turn to the argument that
purports to show that symmetrical color experience spaces are an
impossibility. That argument rests, as
I said, on the claim that the phenomenal character of experiences is determined
by the similarity relations they enter into.
But that claim is ambiguous. It
might mean simply that the phenomenal character of any experience in a
creature’s repertoire is determined by its relations of similarity and
difference to the other experiences in its repertoire. If you fix the phenomenal character of those
other experiences, and fix its relations of similarity and difference to them,
then you fix its phenomenal character.
So, e.g., if an experience has just the similarity and difference relations
to my experiences of red, blue, etc. that my experience of green has to them,
then it is phenomenally just like my experience of green. That claim I accept. But it won’t serve Hilbert and Kalderon’s
purposes, because there is nothing in it to rule out the possibility of a
symmetrically structured experience space.
What they require is the stronger claim that given a set of experiences,
the holding of the similarity and difference relations amongst them constitutes
their having the phenomenal characters they have. This does rule out symmetrically structured experience
spaces. In such an experience space
there would have to be pairs of experiences whose members would be indiscernible
by any description of the set of experiences to which they belong which speaks
only of the similarity and differences relationships holding among its members
– and on the view of Hilbert and Kalderon, and of Austen Clark, the supposedly
different members of these pairs would have to be identical.[18] Clark suggests that to define terms for the
qualitative states that figure in the experience space “one must form the
Ramsey sentence for the entire structure of qualitative relations, and
associate each particular term with a particular Ramsey correlate” (p. 18). This works only if the similarity and
difference relationships give the space an asymmetrical structure; applying it
to a symmetrical space identifies qualitative states that are supposed to be
distinct. So the assumption that
qualitative states are relational yields the result that a symmetrically
structured experience space is impossible.
I suspect that such
plausibility as the relational view has derives partly from the failure to
distinguish it from the first reading of the claim that the phenomenal
character of experiences is determined by their similarity and difference
relations to other experiences. On the
first reading that claim simply relies on the point that phenomenal similarity
and difference are internal relations that hold in virtue of the phenomenal
character of their terms, and does not imply that phenomenal characters are
themselves relational properties. The
view that they are relational properties seems to me phenomenologically
implausible. And it goes against it
that, as I claimed earlier, it seems conceivable that we could discover on
behavioral grounds that a creature had a symmetrically structured color
experience space.[19]
Rejecting
the relational view allows the possibility of symmetrically structured color
quality spaces, and with it, I think, the possibility of behaviorally
undetectable spectrum inversion involving creatures with such spaces. It also allows the possibility of creatures
with color quality spaces having the same asymmetrical structure as our own who
are such that none of their color experiences are phenomenally like any
of ours. This would be a case of what
has been called “alien qualia.” Like
the possibility of spectrum inversion, this possibility is incompatible with
standard representationalism. But my
rejection of standard representationalism does not rest on the rejection of the
relational view and the possibilities it allows. For the possibility of the kind of spectrum inversion I have
argued to be possible in the case of creatures with asymmetrically structured
color experience spaces is compatible with the relational view; it is compatible with the view of Hilbert and
Kalderon, and of Austen Clark, that the phenomenal character of color
experiences is purely a matter of their occupying a certain place in a similarity
ordering. And that possibility is
incompatible with standard representationalism.
One
view about spectrum inversion I have not yet addressed is the view, held by
some standard representationalists, that there could be cases of spectrum
inversion but that these would involve systematic misperception of the colors
on the part of one of the parties. I
will begin my second lecture with a discussion of this; that will prepare the
ground for the presentation of my own version of representationalism.
[End of first Whitehead lecture.]
In my first lecture I made a case against the view I have called standard representationalism – the view that says that the phenomenal character of perceptual experiences consists in their objective representational content, and in the case of color experiences consists in their representing certain colors. This view denies the possibility of spectrum inversion, except on an understanding of it on which it would require that one of the invertees be a systematic misperceiver of the colors. I argued that this view has no satisfactory response to what I called the objective explanatory gap problem, the problem of how we can reconcile the perceived nature of the colors with what we believe about the physical causes in objects of our color perceptions, and, what goes with this, no satisfactory response to the considerations that suggest that the way we perceive the colors, the way things look to us with respect to color, is partly a function of the nature of our perceptual system. The best hope for standard representationalism as a way of dealing with the latter involves what I called the “selection gambit,” which says that the nature of our perceptual system selects certain objective properties to be the colors, and certain relations of similarity and difference to be the relations of color similarity and difference. And I believe that this is on the right track. But I argued that, contrary to standard representationalism, this allows for the possibility of spectrum inversion. More specifically, it allows for spectrum inversion involving perceptual systems, such as our own, that have asymmetrical color quality spaces. It allows this because it allows the sets of properties selected to be the colors by different perceptual systems to overlap in certain ways. I also argued that, contrary to certain views about perceptual content, it is possible for there to be perceptual systems with symmetrical color quality spaces, and that it is possible in principle that there should be behaviorally undetectable spectrum inversion involving perceptual systems of this sort. But the latter argument is not needed to show that standard representationalism is mistaken; the earlier one will suffice.
An
idea I did not take up last time is that behaviorally undetectable spectrum
inversion is possible but would involve systematic misperception on the part of
one of the parties to the inversion. So
if Jack and Jill are spectrum inverted relative to each other, one or the other
of them will be perceiving red things as green, blue things as yellow, and so
forth. This is a view compatible with
standard representationalism; while the two perceivers standardly get phenomenally different perceptions from the
same objects, this difference in phenomenal character goes with a difference in
representational content; that is why one of them must be misperceiving. On some versions of this view, it may be
that both perceivers have correct beliefs about the colors of
things. But if, for example, both report
that ripe tomatoes look red, and mean this in the “phenomenal” and not just the
“epistemic” sense of “looks,” then one of them must be mistaken about the
character and content of her experience.
Let
our invertees be Jack and Jill.
Michael Tye, in discussing this case, allows that in the “epistemic” and
“comparative” senses of “looks,” ripe tomatoes will look red to both Jack and
Jill – to both they will look as if they were red, and in both cases the way
they look will be like the way standard red things look to the person in
question. But in the “phenomenal”
sense, ripe tomatoes will look red to one of them and green to the other. Let Jack be the one to whom ripe tomatoes
look green. It is not to be expected, of course, that Jack will say that
ripe tomatoes look green – he certainly won’t if the inversion is behaviorally
undetectable. But if he says that they
look red, meaning this in the phenomenal sense, he will be misreporting the
contents of his experiences. According
to some proponents of this view, this
needn’t mean that the phenomenal character of his experience is introspectively
inaccessible to him – only that he does not fully understand the meanings of
his public language color words.[20]
One might instead suppose that in his idiolect “red” means green and “green”
means red. Then he could be correct
when he says “It looks red” of the tomato.
But then, unless we suppose that there is an equivocation in his use of
color words that he doesn’t notice, his attributions of the colors red and
green to objects, although phonologically just like those Jill makes to the
same objects, would be systematically false.
Given that Jack and Jill learned their color language in the same way,
the idea that Jack’s color attributions are systematically false while Jill’s
are systematically true cannot be taken seriously. And to my mind the idea that Jack’s color attributions, and color
beliefs, are true, to the extent that Jill’s are, and yet are systematically
produced by misperceptions of the colors, is equally implausible. But let me pursue this a bit further.
The
obvious question to ask about this view is: supposing that red things look to
Jack the way green things look to Jill, and likewise for other pairs of colors,
what could make it true that it is Jack, rather than Jill, who is
systematically misperceiving things?
There is of course the answer: what makes this true is that red things
look red to Jill and green to Jack, that green things look green to Jill and
red to Jack, and so on. But the question
is, what makes that true? This
is the same as the question, in virtue of what do Jack’s and Jill’s color experiences have representational
contents that make Jill’s experiences normally veridical and Jack’s experiences
normally illusory? If the contents of
their experiences were fixed by what causes experiences of certain sorts under
optimal viewing conditions, then the experiences Jack expresses by saying “It
looks red” should be alike in content to those Jill expresses by saying “It
looks red.”[21] And that of course is contrary to the idea
that Jill’s experiences are veridical and Jack’s are illusory.
It
is obvious that what is needed here is an externalist view of the determination
of the color content of perceptual experiences. And it must be an externalist view that allows that the
experiences of different subjects can differ in color content even though the
subjects are identically embedded in identical environments. Such a view can be found in Fred Dretske and
is appealed to by Michael Tye in his account of how a “pure
representationalist” can allow the possibility of the sort of spectrum
inversion in which one of the parties systematically misperceives.[22] Dretske holds that a perceptual state
represents a certain property if it has the function of indicating that
property. And what bestows this
function is natural selection. In our
example, both Jack and Jill have experiences that indicate the presence of something
red. But whereas Jill’s experience has
the function of indicating the presence this property, and so represents its
presence, Jack’s experience is of a type that has the function of indicating
the presence of something green, and so represents, falsely, the presence of
that property. Jack is descended from
creatures who evolved in such a way as to bestow on the relevant state the
function of indicating the presence of green things; but at some point there
was a mutation that resulted in, as it were, some wires getting crossed; the
result was that in the ensuing lineage the properties indicated by experiences
were different from those they had the function of indicating, and so different
from those they represent.
Michael
Tye thinks that it is metaphysically possible for spectrum inversion, of the
sort that involves misperception on the part of one of the invertees, to hold
between microphysical duplicates. We
can hardly have Jack and Jill as microphysical duplicates, so let’s make it
Jules and Jim. Suppose that Jim is the
one who systematically misperceives.
What we must suppose here, apparently, is something like this. In the remote past there evolved two sets of
creatures, who were alike except that the physical states that in one of them
had the function of indicating red had in the other the function of indicating green,
and likewise for other pairs of colors.
Despite this difference, it was true in both groups back then that the
colors indicated were normally those represented, so on the standard
representationalist view there was initially no inversion with respect to
phenomenal character. Jules descended
from members of one of these groups, and Jim descended from members of the
other. At some point in the lineage
that led to Jim there was a mutation that made subsequent creatures in that
lineage physically just like creatures descended from the other group, and just
like them with respect to what properties are indicated by their sensory
states, but not like them with respect to what properties are represented by
these states. Eventually this resulted
in Jules and Jim as microphysical duplicates, with Jules as someone who sees
the colors of things as they are and Jim as someone who systematically
misperceives them.
This
is, of course, a radically externalist view about phenomenal character. Not only does the phenomenal character of
experiences not supervene on the intrinsic physical states of their subjects;
it also does not supervene on the total physical state of the world at a
time. And we can leave out the word
“physical” here – it does not supervene on the total state of the world at a
time, even if there is more to that state than the way things are
physically. My visual experience’s
having the phenomenal character it does
– indeed, its having any phenomenal character at all – is partly an
historical fact, one about my evolutionary history.
This is precisely the sort
of view one needs if one holds that cases of spectrum inversion are possible
but that in such cases some of the parties to the inversion systematically
misperceive the colors. I do not know
how to show that this view is wrong. It
seems to me absurd on the face of it.
But let me add an embellishment to the story just told which I think
highlights its absurdity. Let Jack and
Jill be the brother and sister of, respectively, Jules and Jim. Unlike their siblings, they are of course
not microphysical duplicates – but they are as much alike physically as
siblings of different sexes normally are, despite being spectrum inverted
relative to each other. And of course
on the view under consideration, one of them systematically misperceives the
colors. Suppose Jack and Jill marry,
and have a child – call him Tom. And
suppose Tom is viewing a ripe tomato.
The visual state he is in is one that in his ancestors on one side
evolved to have the function of indicating red things, and in his ancestors on
the other side evolved to have the function of indicating green things. Which color does it represent, red or
green? Or is there perhaps no fact of
the matter about what color it represents, and no fact of the matter about what
phenomenal character his experience has?
From
now on I will assume that it is possible in principle for there to be cases of
spectrum inversion in which the invertees are equally good perceivers of the
colors. What I want to show next is
that while allowing this possibility is incompatible with standard
representationalism, it requires acceptance of a different version of
representationalism.
[1] See my 2001.
[2] Levine, 1983 and 1993.
[3] Sellars, 1963.
[4] Boghossian and Velleman, 1989 and 1991.
[5] Moore, 1922.
[6] See Harman 1990, Lycan 1996, Tye 2000, Dretske 1995, Byrne 1997, and Hilbert 1997 and 2000.
[7] Campbell, 1993, p. 268
[8] See Hardin, 1988, and Block, 1999.
[9] See Hilbert, 1987 and Gibbard, 1996.
[11] Clark 2000.
[12] But it should be noted that in his 1992 Hilbert opposes the view that “different organisms use their color vision to detect different properties” (p. 153).
[13] I think this corresponds roughly to Austen Clark’s distinction between the space of “phenomenal properties” and the space of “qualitative” properties. See his 2000, p. 4.
[14] What in the first instance the experience types will be paired with are with are not the colors themselves but color-like properties I call “appearance properties” (see my second lecture). In the experience of a particular subject these will be closely associated with the colors, but what appearance property one sees in perceiving a particular color will depend on the background, the intensity of the light, and the adaptational state of the observer. My second lecture discusses the relation between colors and appearance properties. In the present discussion I assume, for sake of simplicity, a direct pairing of experience-types with colors.
[15] See Harrison, 1973, and Hardin, 1997.
[16] For this and related points, see Hardin 1997.
[17] Dennett 1993, p. 927, quoted by Hilbert and Kalderon 2000, p. 207.
[18]Hilbert and Kalderon seem to think that all of the experiences in a symmetrically structured experience space would have to have the same relational properties of this sort, and so the same phenomenal character. Here they seem to have forgotten that the similarities among color experiences would be along several dimensions, including one corresponding to saturation; even in a symmetrical experience space some experience would stand in different relations than others – e.g., some would be maximally saturated, some not. I am indebted to Aaron Zimmerman for pointing this out.
[19]I think that if, as I have claimed, we could discover creatures with symmetrically structured experience spaces, we could discover that two such creatures were spectrum inverted relative to each other. What in the first instance seems empirically discoverable is a case of intrasubjective inversion involving such an experience space – a case in which someone’s color experience at one time is inverted relative to that same person’s color experience at a different time. For an account of how we might discover a case of intersubjective inversion, see Shoemaker 1994a. For doubts, see Stalnaker 1999.
[20] See Hilbert and Kalderon 2000, p.
[21] Here “optimal conditions” includes only conditions whose obtaining supervenes on the intrinsic properties and relations instantiated at the time in question – they do not include, as they do for Michael Tye (2000), such things as the creature’s system performing as it evolved to perform.
[22] See Dretske, 1995, and Tye, 2000.